Review of:
Maria Assad, Reading with Michel Serres: An Encounter with
Time. SUNY Press, 1999.
- Michel Serres is one of the few philosophers who can genuinely lay
claim to the title of "specialist generalist" (Dale and Adamson).
He began his adult life in the merchant navy, going on to study physics
and mathematics. He wrote his first book on Leibnitz, followed by the
Hermes series which is comprised of five volumes intersecting literature,
science, and philosophy, and later, studies on Emile Zola, Jules Verne,
Lucretius, the history of Rome, the origins of geometry, and the future of
education. In all he has published more than twenty-five books in the last
thirty years, about five of which have been translated into English. At
present he is Professor in History of Science at the Sorbonne and
Professor in the Department of French and Italian at Stanford University.
- Michel Serres's numerous books provide a
multidisciplinary approach that brings together the study of literature,
philosophy, ecology, poetry, and modern scientific thought. He has been
envisioned by many as a voyager between the arts and the sciences, an
"enigmatic ventriloquist, at once so close and so absent" (Delcò
229), a thinker, as theorist and critic Maria Assad states, who "invents"
through translation, communication, and metaphor. Reading Serres can be a
"reading challenge" (9). After all, Serres produces books made of
other books that, he claims, have nothing to do with invention or
creativity. In Serres's vision, humans belong to the world in a simple,
fundamental sense; ultimately, he insists, "nothing distinguishes me
ontologically from a crystal, a plant, an animal" (Hermes
83). So how and why can we read him in this context? While these
proclamations clearly serve a rhetorical function, they also bring to the
surface a strong undercurrent of Serres's thought: a desire to efface the
edge of difference between language and representation, to fuse knowledge
and being.
- "In science," Werner Heisenberg
states, "the object of research is no longer nature in itself but rather
nature exposed to man's questioning, and to this extent man here also
meets himself" ("Representation" 131). As Norbert Wiener explains in his
book Cybernetics, this development devastated the
positivistic tendencies of "that still quasi-Newtonian world of Gibbs"
(92). It replaced that semi-classical view of time and order "by one in
which time... can in no way be reduced to an assembly of deterministic
threads of development." Or in other words, "There is no set of
observations conceivable which can give us enough information about the
past of a system to give us complete information as to its future" (93).
According to Serres, human history has been constructing--through
religions, mythologies, traditions, and cultures, and above and beyond any
individual biological death--what he calls a "collective immortality" in
the historical sense of this expression. This construct functions on the
basis of two interconnected activities in space and time: efficient
operating techniques construct the world; sociocultural technologies
construct time. This formula defines our episteme as a dynamical system
for which the information of its state is given by the "operative
techniques" (of pre-Cartesian and modern natural sciences); its evolution
over time (its dynamic), on the other hand, is initiated and nurtured by
"the sociocultural technologies" (the human sciences) (Assad 110-11).
Assad's book on time is devoted to what Serres would call a
passage between science and literature. "New" knowledge lies in
the inbetween, or the passage between fixed points of knowledge.
In this challenging context, Reading with Michel Serres is a
provocative look at Serres's use of time in his encyclopaedic narrative
using "dynamical" systems theory. The grouping of the chosen texts is
intended, as the author states in her introduction, to provide "a global
approach to Serres's thought, so that a progressive development becomes
visible, from chaotic multiple to circumstances, to dynamical statues, to
a portrait of dynamical cultural systems that create time as an operating
factor in their inventive drive" (Assad 5).
- The central problem for contemporary philosophy is to
relate to one another the varying conceptions of time that are developing in
individual disciplines. The different approaches to this task are embedded
in the following three basic tendencies that define the contemporary
philosophy of time: "unification tendency," "pluralization
tendency," and "tendency to relativize and historize time"
(Sandbothe).
- Reading with Serres: An Encounter with Time
provides a blueprint of Serres's work on time dynamics. Its six chapters
comprise an assessment of Serres's works arranged in an overlapping
pattern. Time, Assad claims, is no longer thought of as a parameter adding
something to a system from the outside, nor is time a purely
historical force that Serres argues is the source of inherently violent
foundations of our episteme. Formulating a kind of epistemological
principle of uncertainty, Paul Ricoeur states that any meditation on time
"'suffers,' quite simply, from not really being able to think time" (261).
This failure is directly related to an intrinsic "hubris that
impels our thinking [notre pensée] to posit itself as the
master of meaning" (261). In Time and Narrative, Ricouer
cautions against the hubris of reason but adds that an outright rejection
of reason invites "obscurantism" leading to deceptive cognitive processes
engaged in an intellectual free-for-all. "The mystery of time is
equivalent to a prohibition directed against language. Rather it gives
rise to the exigence to think more and to speak differently" (274). This
statement reflects the issues at the center of Serres's cycle of writings
on time. Ricouer's appeal for a new discourse capable of broaching time in
its mysterious working also bears a striking resemblance to Mitchell
Feigenbaum's insistence that insights gained through recent dynamical
systems theories "completely change the way to know something" (Assad
164). Both philosopher and mathematical physicist address the same
issue--that is, that purely analytical methodology is no longer sufficient
or even applicable. Possibilities for a new mode of thinking are forcing
themselves upon the philosophical and scientific consciousness.
- Serres's writings, for which Assad's study
attempts to provide a dynamical reading practice, recuperate Ricouer's
dilemma and enlarge its scope. Serres's overriding premise for the texts
discussed is a kind of bracketing of analytical methods. By leaving the
straight path of philosophical and scientific inquiry and opting instead
for a "visiting" of circumstantial spaces, Serres reinstates a "method"
that had been relegated long ago to the fictional, irrational, or
emotive-intuitive spheres of perception. The convergence of different
vocabularies of time is, from Richard Rorty's perspective, by no means
proof of an intrinsic coincidence between natural and historical time.
The transfer of the vocabulary of historical time from the context of
human self-description into the realms of the natural world, as well as
the mathematically operational implementation of time, illustrate only
the historical ability to adopt inner flexibility and contextual feedback
even in a highly attuned vocabulary such as that found in physics and
mathematics. In Rorty's view, the different vocabularies that we use for
differing purposes and in varying contexts are to be understood as
neither convergent in an intrinsic sense, nor as essentially
incommensurate in a phenomenological sense. Rather, they are themselves
subject to change over time, through which they become related and
disjoined in various ways according to the various historical situations
that arise.
- The radical temporalization of time that is
expressed in these deliberations is noted in Robert Musil's The Man
Without Qualities.
The train of events is a train unrolling its rails ahead of itself. The
river of time is a river sweeping its banks along with it. The traveller
moves about on a solid floor between solid walls; but the floor and the
walls are being moved along too, imperceptibly, and yet in very lively
fashion, by the movements that his fellow-travellers make. (174)
- Assad introduces the concept of unification tendency in
the first two chapters by presenting accounts of historical time, the
natural clock, and their effects upon "our epistemological conscious, in
order to underscore by contrast the other 'new' time emerging from beneath
the guise of tropes" (10). The protagonists of this unification tendency
are convinced that time's validity is that of being a new Archimedean
Point that unifies our everyday experience of the self and the world with
our academic theories about nature and man. This point of unification,
they contend, has been emphasized time and time again in philosophy (by
Bergson, Schelling, and Whitehead, among others), but has been ignored by
science and technology.[1] It wasn't
until the second half of the twentieth century that a global time concept
was developed and mathematically implemented at the interface between the
applied and pure sciences within the framework of "self-organization" or
"autopoeitic" theories. According to the proponents of the unification
tendency, this new conception of time enables the old duality between
natural time and historical time to be overcome and resolves the conflict
between physical, biological, and philosophical approaches to time that
characterized the first half of the twentieth century.
- Assad suggests that Serres's understanding of the linear
time of historical consciousness draws upon René Girard's theory of
the mimetic desire that lurks behind the scapegoat mechanism. For Girard,
desire for a beloved object (or person) is always the imitation of
another's desire for the same object. The scapegoat as trope is considered
both a malevolent and benevolent outsider. "Society is thus founded on an
act of violence by exclusion, while history is the chain of repetitive
imitations of this act" (Assad 11). Girard sees the formation of the
sacred in the linear time of founding exclusions. Serres sees this same
juxtaposition of violence and the sacred, but he locates the essence of
evil as such at the core of repetitive gestures of exclusion. To overcome
evil, Serres proposes an inventive effort: "to achieve this, the linearity
of historical time has to be replaced by a new time" (11). The loss of
repetition in Serres's work (inherent in the nonlinearity of chaotic
systems) becomes the weapon of inventive thought to combat stasis.
Reading with Serres makes frequent reference to nonlinear
dynamics, a theory presently at the forefront of emergent
conceptualization of time.
- The German theoretician of time, Herman Lübbe,
observed,
that even the temporal structure of historicality, which according to
Heidegger and the hermeneutic theory which followed him, results
exclusively from the subject's relationship to itself, which constitutes
meaning, is in reality a structure belonging to all open and dynamic
systems which is indifferent to the subject matter. (qtd. in Sandbothe 1)
Lübbe's convergence theorem can be supported by the deliberations of
Ilya Prigogine:
Whatever the future of these ideas, it seems to me that the dialogue
between physics and natural philosophy can begin on a new basis. I don't
think that I can exaggerate by stating that the problem of time marks
specifically the divorce between physics on one side, psychology and
epistemology on the other.... We see that physics is starting to overcome
these barriers. (qtd. in Sandbothe 1)
- In Assad's chapter "Time Promised: Reading
Genèse" (Genèse is Serre's
meditation on
noise), she investigates the transition or mutation of "noise" and the
"multiple." Serres provides a framework for understanding how ordered
complexity, information, even meaning, can arise from interaction with
disorder. By noise is meant not loud or obnoxious sounds but
that which gets mixed up with messages as they are sent. Noise causes
loss of information in transmitted messages, but in systems in
which message transmission is but a component function, the variety
introduced by noise can come to be informative and meaningful in another,
emergent context. The "multiple" is a "new object for philosophy" that
Serres is "offering to be sounded and perhaps fathomed" by his readers
(Serres, Genesis 2); it is an aggregate or "a set undefined
by elements or boundaries. Locally, it is not individuated; globally, it
is not summed up" (4). These concepts become in Genesis the
first metaphoric paradigm in a chain of tropes that Serres continues to
weave into a series of epistemological writings providing the model for a
new concept of time.
- Assad claims that the shift from the French
"bruit" to noise (from a clearly modern word to a term more or
less effaced by historical time) is symptomatic of a development in
Serres's materialist notion of time. Bruit becomes part of
"noise," which the author revives from the old French where it meant
disorderly furor as well as noise. Built into the very concept of
noise--as a set of interference phenomena and as the parasite
that triples as an abusive guest/a parasitic organism/static noise--is the
overriding notion of the excluded middle or third (Assad 18).
Genèse, according to Assad, is an attempt to give
prime billing to the exclusion, but without its conceptual dominance or
accrued power: "Disorder, chaos, and the clamor of human relations have
to be discovered, uncovered and accepted as valid fields of contemplation
without squeezing them into a straight jacket" (18). The "multiple" is the
metaphorical vehicle Serres chooses to guide his reader through chaos,
that is, to have her confront the complexity of the most common elements
of his world. The metaphoric nature of this iterative process prevents it
from becoming a linear progression and assures an open-ended variability.
- Assad makes two observations concerning Serres's vision
of time. First, both the static and the "dynamical" are expressed by
"stability," the latter by a "new stability." Second, the statue as the
paradigm of the stagnant static that Serres consistently aligns with death
as its telos is contrasted to a turbulent state that is "a median state
between a slightly redundant order and pure chaos" (Assad 120). The enigma
of time is thus not really resolved. History as a destructive time is
described by "noise" deformed into rumor and dull repetition. On the other
hand, "noise" of la belle noiseuse promises dissipative
possibilities. For Serres, la belle noiseuse is the passage from
the pre-phenomenological primal soup to our phenomenological ordered
world. She is the processing of all possibilities, not their sum or
reservoir. Since she is neither chaos nor order, she is what dynamicists
call a "phase transition," that fuzzy state when a system is at the
threshold of a phase change (Paulson 404-416). In
Genèse, the static as stagnant redundancy and the
dynamical aspect of turbulence are hesitatingly wedded in a statue that
turbulently rises and fades from the reader's grasp: a fluctuation, an
oscillating state between the pre-phenomenological and the phenomenon.
Phenomenological time, consisting in a dimension of future, past, and
present, is explained by Ricoeur as being appropriate only
in narrative. And time in the narrative "refiguration" itself becomes
comprehensible only up to a point. For Ricoeur, Emmanuel Levinas's and
Michael Theunissen's time marks the "mystery" in our thought that denies
representation in that our existence irrevocably pervades our thinking.
- Assad's chapters "Time Immortal" and "Time Empirical"
address Serres's Détachment and Les cinq
sens, a series of fables and an exploration of the five senses.
Serres's philosophy of circumstance shifts from paradigms of fluid
mechanics and passages to parasitism and tropes of topological landscapes.
Assad provides close readings of the horizontal (transcendent) and
vertical (static) planes from Chinese farmers and kite flying to the myth
of Orpheus. Time in Les cinq sens is understood as
infinitesimal "differentials" that together cannot be totalled up; they
are non-integrable. Always inchoate, they are local events we grasp or
"suppose" through our senses. Time for Serres percolates rather
than flows; it is unpredictable, unmeasurable, and unintegrable.
Far from flowing in laminar and continuous lines, like a well-behaved
river under a bridge, upstream to downstream, time descends, turns back on
itself, stops, starts, bifurcates ten times, divides and blends, caught up
in whirlpools and counter-currents, hesitant, aleatory, uncertain and
fluctuating, multiplied into a thousand beds like the Yukon river.
Sometimes time passes, sometimes not; but when it passes, it does so as if
through a colander... and this filter or percolator supplies the best
model for the flow of time. (Serres, "Turner" 15)
- According to Serres, "time can be schematised by a
crumpling, a multiple, foldable diversity" (Conversations
59). Out of this foldability emerges, then, a related phenomenon:
topological time materializes itself in a spatially foldable "nearness."
Serres demonstrates his point through the example of a sketch on a
handkerchief:
If you take a handkerchief and spread it out in order to iron it, you can
see in it certain fixed distances and proximities. If you sketch a circle
in one area, you can mark out nearby points and measure far-off distances.
Then take the same handkerchief and crumple it, by putting it in your
pocket. Two distant points suddenly are close, even superimposed. If,
further, you tear it in certain places, two points that were close can
become very distant. This science of nearness and rifts is called
topology, while the science of stable and well-defined distances is called
metrical geometry.... It is simply the difference between the topology
(the handkerchief) is folded, crumpled, shredded) and geometry (the same
fabric is ironed out flat).... As we experience time--as much in our inner
sense as externally in nature, as much as le temps of history as
le temps
of weather--it resembles this crumpled version much more than the flat,
overly simplified one. (60)
- As a percolating sheet wrapping all circumstances,
topological time is thus spatially foldable, hence enfolding a temporal
nearness. In Serres's "timing of space, time sheds its last distinctions,
past, present, and future become one" (Assad 9). For Serres, in this sense,
the past is, and has never been, out-of-date.[2]
- "Time Dynamical" and "Time Inventive" make use of
simulations of nonlinear dynamical models. Statues and
Le Tiers-Instruit teem with dense metaphorical strings of
apologues that make, at times, for difficult reading. In
Statues, Serres makes a mental leap that allows him to
examine the statue functioning not as static entity but as a dynamical
system.
The statue of Molière's Commander in the last chapter of
Hermès I: La communication is the first
figure with which Serres models the full authority of the stable and
immutable Law, and against which he pits Dom Juan's shifty logic and
maneuvering. The Commander's shadow looms large in Serres's texts on
communication where any argument, pointing to stagnation, rigidity,
stability, repetition, thesis, unitary, or binary constructs, is
ultimately expressed in analogies involving statues or statue-like
phenomena. The statue as the incarnation of absolute immobility, or as
rigid perfection no longer in need of inventive improvements, haunts the
writings of the philosopher of communication. It is the spectre of death,
the totality of stability and of absence of variability. It is Serres's
model of evil. At the heart of the most static and stagnant of all his
discursive tropes, Serres discovers a complexity and an inventive power
where the absence of repetitive instants invites continuous new findings.
(Assad 168-9)
The many functions of the statue are presented in the narrative via a
series of descriptive portraits of historical/cultural phenomena that
trace out dynamical behavior. Assad invites the reader to consider the
paradoxical point where Serres's quest for a true understanding of time,
though seemingly farthest away from scientific discourse, parallels the
most recent scientific and mathematical findings concerning nonlinear
dynamical systems.
- Serres's Le Tiers-Instruit is the blueprint
of a dissipative dynamical system couched in a theatrical setting of a
Harlequin-prologue. The Harlequin is Serres's epistemological model for a
strange attractor. On a computer screen the strange attractor can be
traced out as a basin toward which the trajectory of a dynamical system's
orbit converges while looping erogodically through its phase-space. In the
text, this looping is discursively portrayed by the harlequinesque
métis, a chaotic body or half-breed who goes on halving
himself like a Cantor set or a Koch curve ("middle third"), which links to
Serres's neologism of the "middle-instructed."[3] The third element with Serres is neither "this nor
that"; it is both and neither. According to Serres, "the real passage
occurs in the middle" (Troubadour 5). Whether Serres talks
about the left-handed child (himself) taught to write like a right-handed
child, or the swimmer who arrives at the middle of a stream where he
enters a space that is neutral in distance to both shorelines, all are
harlequinseque in their dilemma; they arrive at a point where commonly
accepted definitions fail, where all directions and meanings are equally
valid (Troubadour 7). To learn to live or pass in this
"middle-ground" is what Serres calls an "apprenticeship for the making of
the third."
- Assad's final chapter, "Time and Earth," deals with
The Natural Contract, revealing a relationship between time
as a "natural" phenomenon and the question of right as an expression of
the human contractual conscious. Serres's notion of the natural contract
grows out of his work on Lucretius and Epicurean philosophy, which opens a
passage between social contract and natural contract. The appeal of the
Lucretian model for Serres clearly stems from its positing an essential
freedom at its base. Assad's project is to present dynamical time in the
most applicable and concrete form we are capable of understanding today,
namely the social contract, sealing a union between the human subject and
the physical object. It puts into a proposal with practical applications
for the future what Serres has gleaned from an ancient fabled setting
called "Ulysses' circum-navigations," a nonlinear dynamical system that
invents new knowledge at every turn, without closure. We call it "epic"
and ignore the fact that what we so designate is the story of a new
time (Serres, Les cinq 290). In The Natural
Contract, Serres searches out a "strong and simple science [that]
will tell me the moment of denouement, of being stripped bare and untied,
the moment of true casting off... from this earth toward the void"
(Natural 115).
- The inner reflexivity in the modern apprehension of time
is reminiscent of Kant and Heidegger. Bruno Latour, Serres's conversation
partner in Conversations on Science, Culture, and Time (1995),
presses him on the issue of the use of time in his writings. Latour sees
in the twisting of time one of the reasons for the intellectual jarring
experienced by readers who judge Serres's writings to be obscure and
difficult to follow: "This problem of time is the greatest source of
incomprehension, in my opinion" (Serres, Conversations 48).
But Serres points out that in his writings the question is not one of
playing modernity against a past that has been used and is done with. In
other words, his juxtaposing of text, authors, and myths into one time
frame is not a juxtaposing of "times" expressed as past, present, and
future, all lumped together. "I want to be able to understand time and, in
particular, a self-same time" (46). To illustrate the nature of
his contemporaneity that seems to situate him outside of time, Serres
points once again to Lucretius who,
in his own time, really was already thinking in terms of flux,
turbulence, and chaos, and, second, that through this, he is part of
our era, which is rethinking similar problems. I must change time
frames and no longer use the one that history uses. (47)
- Reading with Serres provides a metaphoric
chain forming feedback mechanisms by which an insight once attained
becomes a metaphoric input for the next, comprising a network of
relations producing an interdisciplinary interface. Time is the symptom of
symptoms:
What's time exactly? One form of time for instance, is a clock time which
is reversible. But I am also in danger of dying because of aging. This is
a second form of time; the time of weakness, the time of old age, the time
of death. This is exactly what constitutes thermodynamic time, the time of
entropy. But this time is irreversible because I am going to death and not
to rebirth. But then I have granddaughters and they are beautiful, they
are far more beautiful then me! This is also irreversible but it is the
time of Darwin. That is, although I am going down to death, the time of
Darwin is coming up to evolution. So you have three times, all very
different: reversible, irreversible minus and irreversible plus. And what
is time? It is the combination of these three. My metaphorical style is a
combination of three results of scientific thought. And what is this
combination? I don't know exactly, it is not scientific thought, it is
metaphysical. Also with chaos theory a new theory of time comes about:
time is indeterministic to the future. So I must think about time with the
instructions of astrononomy, mechanics, thermodynamics biology, chaos
theory and so on. I must study these specialities in order to have a
metaphysics of time. There is not an opposition between scientific thought
and the metaphysical world. (Dale & Adamson)
- Michel Serres shows that culture circulates through
science no less than science circulates through culture. The heart that
keeps this circulatory system flowing is narrative--narratives about
culture, narratives within culture, narratives about science, narratives
within science (Hayles 21). Reading with Michel Serres/An Encounter
with Time is a provocative study of Michel Serres's work for both
Serreseans and those new to his work. At a time where the threat of
disciplinary meltdown seems increasingly to produce a retreat to narrow
specialization, it is rare to encounter work that genuinely dares to think
globally, with all the problems that entails. As Steven Brown states,
"Serres' work dares."
Department of Digital Media
Trinity and All Saints College, University of Leeds
niranabbas@hotmail.com
COPYRIGHT (c) 2002 BY NIRAN ABBAS.
READERS MAY USE PORTIONS
OF THIS WORK IN ACCORDANCE WITH THE FAIR USE PROVISIONS OF U.S. COPYRIGHT
LAW. IN ADDITION, SUBSCRIBERS AND MEMBERS OF SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTIONS MAY
USE THE ENTIRE WORK FOR ANY INTERNAL NONCOMMERCIAL PURPOSE BUT, OTHER THAN
ONE COPY SENT BY EMAIL, PRINT OR FAX TO ONE PERSON AT ANOTHER LOCATION FOR
THAT INDIVIDUAL'S PERSONAL USE, DISTRIBUTION OF THIS ARTICLE OUTSIDE OF A
SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION FROM EITHER THE
AUTHOR OR THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS IS EXPRESSLY FORBIDDEN.
THIS ARTICLE AND OTHER CONTENTS OF THIS ISSUE ARE
AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE UNTIL RELEASE OF THE NEXT ISSUE. A
TEXT-ONLY ARCHIVE OF THE JOURNAL IS ALSO AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE. FOR
FULL HYPERTEXT ACCESS TO BACK ISSUES, SEARCH UTILITIES, AND OTHER VALUABLE
FEATURES, YOU OR YOUR INSTITUTION MAY SUBSCRIBE TO
PROJECT MUSE, THE
ON-LINE JOURNALS PROJECT OF THE JOHNS
HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS.
Notes
1. In an interview with Catherine Dale
and Gregory Adamson, Serres discusses the importance of Whitehead and
Bergson in his work on time and metaphysics. See <http://www.thepander.co.nz/culture/mserres6.php>
2. See Ming-Qian Ma's "The Past Is No
Longer Out-of-Date" (4). The author mentions in "Notes" that the quote in
the title is taken from Serres's and Latour's Conversations
(48).
3. The Koch Curve is an example of a
fractal created by a replacement rule. Such fractals begin with a simple
image. In the case of the Koch curve and its variants, this image is a
straight line. This image is then changed to something else, based on the
replacement rule. The new image contains elements that correspond to
elements in the original image. The replacement rule is then applied to
these portions of the image, creating a more detailed picture. This
process continues indefinitely, creating infinite detail from a simple
picture and a replacement rule. The Cantor set works a similar way.
Consider a line segment of unit length. Remove its middle third. Now
remove the middle thirds from the remaining two segments. Now remove the
middle thirds from the remaining four segments and so on. What remains
after infinitely many steps is a remarkable subset of the real numbers
called the Cantor set, or "Cantor's Dust."
Works Cited
Brown, Steven D. "Michel Serres: Myth, Mediation and the Logic of the
Parasite" (14 May 2000) <http://devpsy.lboro.ac.uk/psygroup/sb/Serres.htm>.
Dale, Catherine, and Gregory Adamson. "A Michel Serres Interview (Part
II)." Pander OS 2.0 <http://www.thepander.co.nz/culture/mserres6.php>.
Delcò, Alessandro. "Michel Serres: Philosophy as an Indeterminate
Essence to be Invented." Trans. Matthew Tiews and Trina Marmarelli.
Configurations 8.2 (2000): 229-234.
Girard, René. Violence and the Scared. Baltimore: John
Hopkins UP, 1977.
Hayles, Katherine N. How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies in
Cybernetics, Literature and Informatics. Chicago:
U of Chicago P, 1999.
Heisenberg, Werner. "The Representation of Nature in Contemporary
Physics." Trans. O. T. Benfey. The Discontinuous Universe.
Ed. S. Sears and G. W. Lord. New York: Basic Books, 1972. 122-135.
Ma, Ming-Qian ."The Past Is No Longer Out-of-Date: Topological
Time and Its Foldable Nearness in Michel Serres's
Philosophy." Configurations 8.2 (2000): 235-244.
Musil, Robert. The Man Without Qualities. Trans. Eithne
Wilkins and Ernst Kaiser. Vol. 2. London: Picador, 1979.
Paulson, William. "On a Dynamic Analysis Of The Textual
Variation of Le 'Chef-Oeuvre Iconnu' by Balzac, Honore
de." Nineteenth-Century French Studies 19.3 (1991):
404-416.
Ricoeur, Paul. Time and Narrative. Trans. Kathleen Blamey and
David Pellauer. Vol III. Chicago: U of Chicago
P, 1988.
Sandbothe, Mike. "The Temporalization of Time in Modern Philosophy."
<http://www.uni-jena.de/ms/ms_time.html>.
Serres, Michel. Hermèes I: La communication. Paris:
Editions de Minuit, 1969.
---. Hermes--Literature, Science and Philosophy.
Ed. Josué V. Harari and David F. Bell. Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins UP, 1982.
---. Les cinq sens. Paris: Grasset, 1985.
---. The Natural Contract. Trans. Elizabeth MacArthur and
William Paulson. Ann Arbor: U of Michigan P,
1995.
---. Troubadour of Knowledge. Trans. Sheila Faria Gloser and
William Paulson. Ann Arbor: U of Michigan P,
1997.
---. "The Case of Turner." SubStance #83, 26.2 (1997): 6-21.
---. Genesis. Trans. Genevieve James and James Nielson. Ann
Arbor: U of Michigan P, 1995.
---. Serres, Michel, with Bruno Latour. Conversations on
Science, Culture, and Time. Trans. Roxanne Lapidus. Ann
Arbor: U of Michigan P, 1995.
Wiener, Norbert. Cybernetics: Or Control and Communication in
the Animal and the Machine. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
1961.
|