Review of:
Slavoj Zizek, The Fragile Absolute, or, Why is the Christian Legacy Worth Fighting For? New York: Verso, 2000.
- In one of the more arresting moments in The Fragile
Absolute, Slavoj Zizek connects the Pauline concept of
agape, commonly known as Christian love, to the closing shot of
Krzysztof Kieslowski's Blue.[1] The shot is a series of tableaux, each focused on a
character somehow related to the life of the film's heroine, Julie. The
tableaux are separated by a formless void in which each seems to float.
After panning through the void from one character to another, the camera
comes to rest on the weeping face of Julie herself. Emotionally paralyzed
by the death of her husband and child, she has moved through the film
untouched by her encounters with those around her. The effect of the
conclusion is to suggest that Julie has delivered herself from paralysis
and once again become a participant in the psychic life of others. Her
tears indicate that "her work of mourning is accomplished, she is
reconciled with the universe; her tears are not the tears of sadness and
pain, but the tears of agape, of a Yes! to life in its mysterious
synchronic multitude" (103). The tone is unusually lyrical for Zizek,
and indeed for cultural theory in general, yet it is easy to recognize the
standard maneuver being executed here. A canonical theoretical (or in
this case theological) text is expounded using a popular text as an
example. In this instance as in previous works, what distinguishes
Zizek's connections from those of most other cultural theorists (aside
from their frequency) is the way the popular text becomes more than mere
illustration. The usual priorities could be said to be reversed; theory
itself seems the subsidiary thing. One might observe in the provocative
tone of overstatement Zizek has mastered that if we examine Paul's
ultimate statement of the nature of agape, the famous passage
from 1 Corinthians 13, it amounts only to a sort of illustration of the
conclusion of Blue (in fact the passage is being sung in the
background). In his attempt to express an affirmation that could overcome
the fragmentation of historical experience, Paul creates a shadowy and
insufficient illustration of the "mysterious, synchronic" truth expressed
by Kieslowski's camera.
- As bracing as such moments are, Zizek's allegiance to a
specific set of theoretical touchstones lets us know that theory, or at
least a certain kind of theory, never remains in the supporting role for
long. Though the tone of the commentary on Blue is
climactic, the work of Zizek's argument is not complete until the book's
final chapter, in which agape itself is connected to Marxist and
psychoanalytic points of reference. Like the use of popular culture, this
argumentative procedure is now familiar. In a sense Zizek reads Paul's
theology much as he has read an array of Western philosophers, notably
Hegel and Schelling. The wide field of application sheds light on the
status of both philosophy and popular culture. Examples from either
sphere gain value insofar as they express, in whatever form, the truths of
the powerful theoretical principles Zizek has formed from his readings of
Marx on the one hand and Lacan and Freud on the other. Working on the
canon of Western philosophy in this way leaves Zizek open to the challenge
that although he has given us new ways to understand Marx, Freud, and
Lacan, he has distorted our view of the raw material on which he operates.
The question of distortion, however, is likely to be more interesting if
we follow Zizek's own habits of investigation and reverse the direction of
inquiry, asking in what ways his own work is affected by his
appropriations. Such a question seems particularly relevant for this
book, his first to give sustained attention to Christian theology. The
question to ask, then, is not how Zizek distorts Christianity but how the
presence of Christianity distorts Zizek. The distortion turns out to have
a familiar shape. By asserting from a perspective one could provisionally
define as secular that Christianity is "worth fighting for," The
Fragile Absolute enters a long-standing set of conflicts between
religion and the secular, and these conflicts determine the shape of the
argument in ways that are at odds with Zizek's own theoretical program.
- As the reading of agape suggests, Zizek's
purpose in this book is to establish parallels between Christian thought
and his own, situated athwart Marxism and psychoanalysis. Despite the
urgency of the project implied by the book's title, however, the parallels
are slow to appear. The preface announces a crisis that precipitates the
need for a consideration of Christianity, namely the rise of
"fundamentalism" in various political and social contexts. After this
announcement, Zizek turns abruptly to the lively ideological critique for
which he is known, focusing his attention on the implications of global
capitalism in a post-Soviet era. Here too Zizek finds a state of crisis,
one which threatens the very possibility of a meaningful Marxism. Then
follows another abrupt turn, this time to the concept of agape in
the writings of Paul. Agape represents for Zizek the part of
Christianity worth saving, the "legacy" that can undo the double bind in
which Marxism is caught. What is particularly striking about the book's
trajectory is the way that Christianity appears first in a threatening
role and then in a fruitful one, nearly vanishing in between. Before it
can appear in a redemptive capacity, it seems, religion must first appear
in the ominous guise of "fundamentalism."
- Alongside Zizek's misguided attacks on "fundamentalism,"
there is a single moment of insight worth mentioning. In a chapter
memorably entitled "Victims, Victims Everywhere," the media portrayal of
conditions in Kosovo is said to illustrate "the paradox of victimization:
the Other to be protected is good insofar as it remains a
victim... the moment it no longer behaves like a victim, but wants to
strike back on its own, it magically turns all of a sudden into a
terrorist/fundamentalist/drug-trafficking Other" (60). Here the figure of
the "fundamentalist" is clearly a fetishized construction, a
simplification structured to serve the interests of Western capitalist
understanding. The target of Zizek's critique is not "fundamentalism" at
all but rather those who use the term unreflectively, dividing Others into
"victims of religious persecution" and "fundamentalist radicals." Such a
critique is certainly long overdue in the context of U.S. discourse, where
accusations of "fundamentalism" are readily directed at groups within the
nation as well as without. Theoretical tasks immediately suggest
themselves. For instance, there is the need to understand the
relationship between familiar images of "fundamentalism" on the home
front--the fanatical terrorist in Contact--and instantly
recognizable images of "Islamic fundamentalism" deployed in films like
Rules Of Engagement. It could be claimed that in popular
film, fundamentalists, as well as victims, are everywhere.
- Unfortunately, and despite this suggestive moment of
critique, fundamentalism as a secular fantasy also has a strong presence
in this book. In fact the preface contains what qualifies as a
classic instance of this fantasy. First there is an indictment of "one of
the most deplorable aspects of the postmodern era," namely "the return of
the religious dimension in all its different guises: from Christian and
other fundamentalisms, through the multitude of New Age spiritualisms, up
to the emerging religious sensitivity within deconstructionism itself."
This alleged return raises the abiding question of "the religious legacy
within Marxism itself" (1). Zizek's approach to this question is, not
surprisingly, an attempt at reversal:
Instead of adopting such a defensive stance, allowing the enemy to define
the terrain of the struggle, what one should do is to reverse the strategy
by fully endorsing what one is accused of: yes, there
is a direct lineage from Christianity to Marxism; yes,
Christianity and Marxism should fight on the same side of the
barricade against the onslaught of the new spiritualisms--the authentic
Christian legacy is much too precious to be left to the fundamentalist
freaks. (2)
This certainly appears to reverse a traditional Marxist position on the
question of religion, but it does so by way of a view of fundamentalism
that could hardly be more predictable. The fundamentalist is the
political "enemy," the one whose dogmatic theological stance not only
justifies but actually requires hostility on the part of the critic.[2]
- The baldness of this declaration is itself something of a
landmark. Never before in a work of cultural theory has the prejudice
against certain forms of religion been expressed so openly, and never have
the specific contours of that prejudice surfaced in such a condensed form.
The self/other antagonism finds clear expression in a language of
boundaries and alliances but also deploys a language of monstrosity. The
choice of the word "freaks" carries the conviction that fundamentalists,
those on the other side of the "barricade," are so utterly other
as to put themselves beyond the reach of analysis. Tied to the image of
the fundamentalist-as-other is an equally significant feature of secular
ideology, namely a historicizing structure that approaches religion by way
of its particular relation to temporality. The familiar Weberian claim
that religion is in decline is the most visible example of this, but Zizek
provides another. If the traditional language of "secularization"
suggests that religion's decline is inevitable, the language of "return"
suggests some tidal rhythm that allows it to keep resurfacing. Though it
might seem that there is a contradiction here between Zizek's claim and
the traditional line, the point of Zizek's claim is not to critique the
traditional position but simply to reverse it. The fact that secular
historicism has trouble accounting for such returns is not itself a cause
of distress, although religion's "return" obviously is. This is not the
first time a claim of return has been uttered, but its use necessitates a
certain degree of forgetfulness.
- The more Zizek's historicizing language about religion is
examined, the less difference there appears to be between the traditional
claim to decline and this latest announcement of return. In Weber's
Protestant Ethic, the stance is one of distance; religion is
made an object of study, and its value is paradoxically derived from the
assumption that it is vanishing. In his conclusion, Weber remarks that
"the idea of duty in one's calling prowls about in our lives like the
ghost of dead religious beliefs" (182). The death of religion is so
deeply presumed that it provides the kind of automatic reference point
necessary for a simile. For Zizek, religion is not simply another element
of culture to be studied and is certainly not vanishing from history. In
fact its ahistoricity relative to other elements of culture, combined with
the abhorrent reality of its "fundamentalist" manifestations, give it a
peculiar and traumatic presence. In taking the fight to Christianity,
insisting that it must be made to confess its alliance with Marxism, Zizek
gives the impression that there is more than an external threat here--not
simply a political challenge but an epistemological problem. It could
certainly be argued that this anxiety is already latent in Weber's
assumption of theoretical distance, the insistence on containing religion
within a framework of historical necessity. Nearly a century after Weber,
religion has demonstrated an unexpected staying power, and the position of
distance collapses. The question that haunts the background is the same.
- In order to function as an assumption, the question
itself has to stay in the background. If made visible, it might
read thus: How can secular thought tolerate the idea that religions
continue to exist at all? More specifically, how can secular thought
approach those forms of faith that make their political presence felt
while subjugating the concerns of history to those of eternity (i.e.,
"fundamentalists")? Once asked, the question smacks of the "immodest
demands of transcendental narcissism" that William Connolly has
ascribed to secular thought (8), a charge that would seem to require
retrenchment of its claims to cultural and epistemological ascendancy.
But in this book, the latest and boldest in a tradition of such immodesty,
the shape of the answer still conceals its question.[3] Clearly, the persistence of religion as a political
and cultural force contradicts secular assumptions. But the self/other
dichotomy created by the image of the "fundamentalist freak" places the
blame for this contradiction on fundamentalists. The frequently declared
"return" of religion, despite what secular thought knows to be true of its
continuing existence, becomes the very evidence that return is
unthinkable. In the tone of Zizek we might say that the fantasy of
fundamentalism works like this: We all know that religion, because it is
in decline, is illegitimate at best and potentially monstrous; therefore,
if it is discovered that religion is not in decline at all and is in fact
not only a living element of culture but a political and intellectual
force as well, this proves beyond a shadow of a doubt just how monstrous
it is!
- Given the circular nature of such assumptions about
fundamentalism, it is not surprising that Zizek does little to
analyze it as such. After the preface, he largely ignores
religion for several chapters, turning instead to the issue that has
always been central to his thought: the relationship between
psychoanalytic conceptions of the subject and Marxist conceptions of
ideology and politics. One of the central claims Zizek makes about
subjectivity, stated here in a vocabulary less explicitly Lacanian than he
has used in the past, is that "the paradox of the subject is that it
exists only through its own radical impossibility, through a 'bone in the
throat' that forever prevents it (the subject) from achieving its full
ontological identity" (28). As always, such formulations are surrounded
by examples (though again, this is not the best word for them) from the
realm of culture and especially popular culture. There is a discussion of
the crucial place of trash or excrement in postmodern art, an analysis of
Coke as the ultimate example of surplus enjoyment, and a reading of the
place of simulation in the constitution of sexual relationships in
My Best Friend's Wedding. In addition to this typical
procedure, however, there is a reconsideration of the whole question of
"radical impossibility" in light of current problems in Marxist thought.
In this book even more than in his previous work, it is clear that for
Zizek psychoanalysis is not merely a way to upgrade Marxism by making it
more sensitive to questions of culture and subjectivity. A
psychoanalytically informed Marxism seems to Zizek the best hope for a
systematic critique of Marxism's weaknesses and failures in the
context of post-Soviet Europe.
- The failure of Communism, Zizek insists, was not the
result of some defeat from without by the forces of capitalism. Instead,
Communism was already "a fantasy inherent to capitalism itself" (18). If
capitalism struggles with the contradictions created by surplus value and
finds itself plunged again and again into crisis, then Communism is the
fantasy that such crises could be abolished forever while the productive
drive of capitalism is retained. In other words, Communism is a fantasy
that the "radical impossibility" of the capitalist economy could be
overcome without altering the structures of desire and enjoyment it
produces. Zizek asserts not only that the progressive/utopian idea of
pushing capitalism toward some final stage into Communism is a trap, but
also that there is no hope of some return to pre-modern conditions which
would do away with capitalist machinery and economics (as Tyler Durden
aspires to do in Fight Club, to mention a film that will no
doubt find its way into Zizek's work in the very near future). Marxism
must continue its work stripped of all its fantasies about a past before
the advent of Capital or about a future that awaits it:
The task of today's thought is thus double: on the one hand, how to
repeat the Marxist "critique of political economy"
without the utopian-ideological notion of Communism as its
inherent standard; on the other, how to imagine actually breaking out of
the capitalist horizon without falling into the trap of returning to the
eminently premodern notion of a balanced, (self)-restrained
society. (19-20)
Needless to say, this double task challenges Marxist theory far more than
the business of critiquing artifacts of popular culture. Having
implicated Marxism in capitalism's "radical impossibility" in the fullest
possible way, Zizek then attempts to work toward a new means of surpassing
that impossibility. It is at this point that religion reappears, this
time in the role of ally.
- Zizek's key move is a transmutation of the problem of
"radical impossibility" that leads back into the realm of theology. The
double bind of Marxist theory, he asserts, has much in common with the
paradox of the law in Christianity and Judaism. The problem of surpassing
the fantasy of Communism without falling into fantasies of historical
regression is seen to parallel the problem of how, finally, to settle the
law's demands. This second double bind is expressed thus:
The "repressed" of Jewish monotheism is not the wealth of pagan sacred
orgies and deities but the disavowed excessive nature of its own
fundamental gestures: that is--to use the standard terms--the crime that
founds the rule of the Law itself, the violent gesture that brings about a
regime which retroactively makes this gesture itself illegal/criminal.
(63)
The "violent gesture" Zizek discusses here is the killing of the lawgiver
that Freud posits in Moses and Monotheism, but it is
translated into "standard terms," that is, into the terms of a Lacanian
discourse that can comprehend the productive drives of capitalism on the
one hand and the cycle of law and transgression on the other. Just as
Marxism is denied both the fantasy of a return to a "premodern" economy
and the hope of a utopian future for capitalism, so Judaism is cut off
from pagan conditions where the regime of the law does not yet exist and
from a future in which the demands of the law could be met once and for
all. Zizek's leap from ideology to theology is a large one, but it is
evidently made in the most serious way. The paradox that structures the
Judeo-Christian economy is posited as a kind of spiritual
proto-capitalism, giving explicit form to Zizek's initial claim of a
"direct lineage from Christianity to Marxism."
- It is clear that Zizek does not think Christianity in any
of its institutional forms provides the solution to Marxism's
dilemma. However, he still finds in Christian theology formulations that
can point the way. The essence of the "authentic Christian legacy" is
found in another passage from Paul, his analysis of the relationship
between law and transgression in Romans 7. Paul's observation that
without law there is no knowledge of sin becomes an exploration of
Christianity as a move to end the cycle of law and transgression. Far
from simply attempting to fill up the structure of Judaic law through
messianic redemption, Christianity seeks to move beyond the structure
altogether. Zizek asks:
What if the Christian wager is not Redemption in the sense of the
possibility for the domain of the universal Law retroactively to
"sublate"--integrate, pacify, erase--its traumatic origins, but something
radically different, the cut into the Gordian knot of the vicious cycle of
Law and its founding transgression? (100)
What enables this cut is agape, which "simultaneously avoids
narcissistic regression and remains outside the confines of the Law"
(112-13). If all this sounds familiar, it is because it makes
Christianity bear such a strong resemblance to a psychoanalytic model of
self-transformation. Zizek even goes so far as to claim that "while it
is easy to enjoy acting in a egoistic way against one's duty, it
is, perhaps, only as the result of psychoanalytic treatment that one can
acquire the capacity to enjoy doing one's duty" (141).[4]
- If we take Zizek's claims simply as a reading of certain
key moments in the writings of Paul, it is difficult to dispute the
plausibility of the resemblance between psychoanalytic treatment and
Christian conversion.[5] But it is
difficult to avoid the thought that there is a pattern of fetishism at
work in a theoretical position that enthusiastically embraces those
elements of Christianity which match psychoanalytic theory while rejecting
what cannot be subsumed with corresponding zeal. Do we not have here an
example of the "double attitude" Freud discusses, which simultaneously
venerates and denigrates the fetish? Are not Zizek's defense of the
"subversive core of Christianity" (119) and his hostility for
"fundamentalist freaks" two aspects of the same construction? Here we see
how the collapse of Weber's theoretical distance brings religion into play
on both sides of the "barrier"; religion is at once a source of
authorization and an uncanny threat. At the same time that it provokes
the most extreme ideological hostility, religion's traumatic status is the
impetus for a struggle over its "legacy," the core value that is the
ostensible prize to be won from "fundamentalism."
- Zizek's way of treating religion in general and
Christianity in particular suggests that before we secular critics declare
ourselves fit to pass judgment on the nature of the "authentic Christian
legacy," we have much to do in the way of understanding the role played by
religion in secular fantasy. In The Fragile Absolute,
religion is made the basis for a solution to a dilemma in Marxist thought,
providing both an enemy to oppose from without and a way to restructure
difficulties from within. The question for secular theory at present is
how to avoid this procedure of deploying religion in the interest
of this or that project. If many of Zizek's moves are examples of what we
should avoid, his concepts of subjectivity nevertheless suggest the
direction we might go from here. Agape, he argues, gives us a
way to "liberate [ourselves] from the grip of existing social reality" by
"renounc[ing] the transgressive fantasmic supplement that attaches us to
it" (149). This renunciation must take the form of "the radical gesture
of 'striking at oneself'" (150), of aiming directly at the object of
desire that grounds subjective and ideological stability. This gesture is
illustrated, not surprisingly, by popular texts: The Shawshank
Redemption, Beloved, Medea, and others.
The line of thought I have been suggesting is meant to serve as another
illustration, one that hits closer to home. The way in which Zizek's
argument is overtaken by the fetish of fundamentalism (and its complement,
the "subversive core") suggests that at the moment secular discourse needs
to "strike at itself," to make the secular and not religion the primary
object of its critique.
- As a beginning, it seems worthwhile to get to work on a
redefinition of the word "secular," which needs to be understood (and has
been used here, I hope) as marking a certain subjective stance
with its own complex psychic life and not simply a set of pre-given
discursive structures. At the same time, the secular will have to be more
rigorously critiqued as an ideology which gives a place for that
subjectivity. Such a redefinition will be greatly helped by the work of
Slavoj Zizek. If his use of "fundamentalism" is cautionary, his
understanding of ideological subjectivity gives us a way forward.
Whatever "forward" means, it will involve neither a renewal of hostilities
with this or that form of religion on the basis of historical presumption
nor a "return," repentant or otherwise, to a theological source of
authorization. The history of such hostilities and returns should now
become the focus. In the realm of critical theory, The Fragile
Absolute is the latest chapter in that history. Caught between a
vision of "the tears of agape" on the one hand and a fear of
"fundamentalist freaks" on the other, it stops short of a recognition of
its own secular ideology.
Department of Literatures in English
Rutgers University
pizzino@fas-english.rutgers.edu
COPYRIGHT (c) 2002 BY CHRISTOPHER PIZZINO.
READERS MAY USE PORTIONS
OF THIS WORK IN ACCORDANCE WITH THE FAIR USE PROVISIONS OF U.S. COPYRIGHT
LAW. IN ADDITION, SUBSCRIBERS AND MEMBERS OF SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTIONS MAY
USE THE ENTIRE WORK FOR ANY INTERNAL NONCOMMERCIAL PURPOSE BUT, OTHER THAN
ONE COPY SENT BY EMAIL, PRINT OR FAX TO ONE PERSON AT ANOTHER LOCATION FOR
THAT INDIVIDUAL'S PERSONAL USE, DISTRIBUTION OF THIS ARTICLE OUTSIDE OF A
SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION FROM EITHER THE
AUTHOR OR THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS IS EXPRESSLY FORBIDDEN.
THIS ARTICLE AND OTHER CONTENTS OF THIS ISSUE ARE
AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE UNTIL RELEASE OF THE NEXT ISSUE. A
TEXT-ONLY ARCHIVE OF THE JOURNAL IS ALSO AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE. FOR
FULL HYPERTEXT ACCESS TO BACK ISSUES, SEARCH UTILITIES, AND OTHER VALUABLE
FEATURES, YOU OR YOUR INSTITUTION MAY SUBSCRIBE TO
PROJECT MUSE, THE
ON-LINE JOURNALS PROJECT OF THE JOHNS
HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS.
Notes
1. Thanks to Larry Scanlon for a timely
word on Pauline scholarship.
2. The majority of this review was
completed before September 11 and I thought it inadvisable to attempt a
revision which would address recent events at length. Suffice it to say
that official and unofficial responses alike have largely conformed to the
generic parameters I describe for "fundamentalism" as a discourse. We
have repeatedly heard the notion that fundamentalism is beyond the reach
of analysis, that it falls into some category of absolute evil which
renders it unworthy of discursive engagement (and eminently worthy of
hostility). Even some responses which attempt to challenge this notion
nonetheless end up reiterating it. Take for example the parallels many
have made between Osama bin Laden and Jerry Falwell. If the impetus of
the parallel is to upset racist and nationalist notions about
fundamentalism, the end result is to establish a more unilateral prejudice
which blocks an understanding of fundamentalism as a discourse (and does
little to get at the roots of racism or nationalism either).
3. I am thinking of Louis Althusser's
discussion of Marx in the opening chapter of Reading "Capital."
Althusser insists that Marx's achievement lies not in his providing more
accurate answers to the questions posed by classical economics but rather
in his ability to perceive the real nature of its questions. So here, the
point is not to differ with Zizek concerning what ought to be done with
the Christian legacy nor suggest a different response to the "return" of
religion. Rather than attempting to answer such questions, the
unexpressed intention of the questions themselves must be examined.
4. This kind of enjoyment would seem also
to be the subject of Blue and particularly of its conclusion.
The music playing in the background as Julie is "reconciled with the
universe" is a piece written by the heroine to celebrate the formation of
the EEC. Throughout the movie she has disavowed authorship of the piece,
but at the last she decides to claim it as her own and complete it. What
strikes a chord with Zizek's view of agape is that Julie does not
act against her duty, as it were, and refuse to complete a work officially
intended to commemorate a new era of capitalism in Europe. Instead, she
actively and passionately embraces the work, though in such a way as to
give it a more particular and more radical meaning in relation to her
life. Such an intensely private political vision raises
questions about the value of agape other than those I discuss
here.
5. Though my concern with Zizek's view of
Christianity is the way it functions as a secular ideology, it is at least
worth mentioning that his "Christian" view of Paul has related problems as
well. By stressing the distinction between Judaism and Christianity in a
way that re-canonizes Paul as a Christian, Zizek makes a highly
contestable theological claim, even if his intentions are only to reclaim
Paul for Lacan, Freud, and Marx.
Works Cited
Althuser, Louis, and Etienne Balibar. Reading "Capital."
Trans. Ben Brewster. New York: Random House, 1970.
Connolly, William. Why I Am Not a Secularist.
Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1999.
Freud, Sigmund. "Fetishism." Trans. Joan Riviere. Sexuality and
the Psychology of Love. Ed. Philip Rieff. New York: Simon &
Schuster, 1963.
Weber, Max. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of
Capitalism. Trans. Talcott Parsons. New York: Routledge, 1992.
|