- This essay begins in the midst of the ongoing dilemma posed by
late-capitalist society and postmodern culture, namely, whether these
remain the ultimate horizon of the contemporary world and whether efforts
to resist, oppose, represent critically, or propose alternatives to the
"cultural dominant" of postmodernism are merely atavistic. Below, I
address some of the challenges to Marxism (as the discourse of the
alternative to and the critique of capitalism par excellence)
posed by the conditions of what Ernest Mandel has famously named "late
capitalism" and by the theoretical discourse of what Dick Hebdige has
called "the posts,"[1] and make a case for
the continued relevance and value of Marxist theory for an ostensibly
post-Marxist, would-be post-ideological period. The developments in the
theory of ideology advanced in Slavoj Zizek's work, focusing on the role
of psychology in the functioning of ideology under conditions of late
capitalism, are then taken as valuable criticisms and revisions of the
Marxist tradition that open useful avenues for critically understanding
American culture and society in recent decades.
Hard Times for Marxism
- The zeitgeist is anti-Marxist to the same extent that it is
antimodern, exhibiting what Jean-François Lyotard calls in
The Postmodern Condition, in what has become one of the great
slogan-definitions of postmodernism, an "incredulity toward
metanarratives" (xxiv), including especially those inherited from the
modern European Enlightenment tradition, such as progress and liberation.
Lyotard's argument in brief: totalizing "master narratives" no longer
function to legitimate and unify knowledge; the postmodern condition is
marked by heterogeneous and radically incommensurable language games;
attempts to reconcile language games through the principle of consensus
are "terrorist" (63). This argument is typical of postmodern neopragmatist
theorizing in that it precludes the kind of large-scale analyses that
would allow adequate attempts to elaborate connections between the
epistemological-linguistic theory he proposes and the social, economic,
and cultural forces to which he only occasionally refers. Obviously,
Marxism is directly challenged in Lyotard's analysis since it
traditionally promotes both a progressive teleology and an emancipatory
politics.
- Other specific challenges to particular Marxist concepts
and protocols are widespread; for example, its utopianism, a topic much
discussed by Fredric Jameson,[2] often
comes under fire. As Clint Burnham notes, the contemporary criticisms of
utopia take two primary forms: "First, the culture doubts the possibility
of some 'better place' than the undoubtedly excellent world of late
capitalism," a criticism that he characterizes as "'bad,' or negative, or
ideological, or neoconservative"; and second, "that culture characterizes
itself as already nonrepresentational by doubting the possibility of
representationalism," a claim that he calls the "'good,' or positive, or
utopian, or postmodern critique of utopia" (2). In either case, a
conception of radical social change toward an imagined (better) future
beyond the capitalist horizon is eradicated. Other Marxist categories and
concepts--everything from the labor theory of value to the claims for
dialectical materialism as a "science" of inquiry[3]--have come under attack in various high theoretical
arguments. Such writings, combined with the collapse of state socialism in
Eastern Europe, have raised the question for leftist intellectuals at the
start of the twenty-first century: why Marxism (still)?
- Burnham offers several answers to this question that are
worth repeating: first, Marxism has for the past thirty years or so found
its "moral legitimacy (for better or for worse)" more in the Western new
social movements of "youth, ecology, feminism, antiracism" and the like
and in the "Third World (from Che to postcolonialism)" than in Eastern
European state socialism; second, Marxism is not a monolithic discourse,
and even during the Soviet era its most significant theorists always
maintained an "independent and skeptical attitude" rather than a blind
allegiance to the Communist party; third, the European revolutions have
demonstrated that "the masses can opt to take control of their own
destinies," invalidating fascist hopes for efficient control, even if
these particular revolts were "as much about consumer goods as... about
freedom"; and fourth, Marxist Third World liberation movements and Marxist
critical analyses of world political-economic situations remain as
relevant as ever in the post-Cold War period (4-5). Regardless of whether
we wish to accept Burnham's claims in their entirety, they certainly
indicate at a minimum that Marxism should not be dismissed as casually as it
often is in the current intellectual climate. For all of its demonstrable
continued relevance, however, Marxism does face difficult times, not least
among intellectuals, as can be seen in the debates over postmodernism in
theoretical circles since the 1970s as well as in the events and
developments that have prompted those debates.
Postmodernism as Post-Marxism
- Most theoretical accounts of postmodernism have focused on various
features of advanced industrialized societies since the end of the second
World War, citing an array of historical transformations as signs of the
birth of a new era. Such trends and events as the detonation of the first
atomic bomb; the proliferation of television; the rise of rock and roll
and youth culture; the first transmissions of images of the earth as seen
from space; the expansion of finance capital and money markets; the
attenuation of the distinction between high art and commercial popular
culture; the development of sophisticated computer technology and the
related nexus of information, power, and profit; the migration of the
middle classes from cities to suburbs; the emergence of new social
movements and political alliances unconstrained by older party
affiliations; the shift in economically advanced regions away from heavy
industrial manufacturing toward a service economy and consumer society,
accompanied by an increased international division of labor; the rise of
nationalist political independence movements; the proliferation of
cynicism and suspicion of traditional narratives of legitimation; the
expansion of multinational corporations; and the consolidation of
reactionary fundamentalist religious and political movements have all been
deemed hallmarks or inaugural moments of postmodern times.
- Different theorists associated with the discourse on
postmodernism have taken different features as definitive and have
approached the topic through different critical frameworks. Lyotard, as
noted above, focuses on epistemology and aesthetics in The
Postmodern Condition, addressing the crisis of legitimation in
contemporary intellectual discourse and advocating the agonistics of
irreconcilable language games. Jean Baudrillard, especially in his work
since the late 1970s, experiments with a postmodern theoretical sociology
that abandons traditional modes of critique and conceptual schemata in
favor of pointed, ironic descriptions of consumer society and mass media.
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari espouse a militant philosophy of
desire, championing the decentered, nomadic, postmodern subject as
"schizo." Jameson, writing on the postmodernism question from within the
Marxist tradition, takes a broad historical perspective, linking
postmodern culture explicitly to changes in the structure of capitalist
political economy in the postwar era.[4]
The differences among the critical perspectives underlying these
positions--in particular the differences between those that treat
postmodernism as an aesthetic style, discursive problematic, or mood of
schizophrenic, contradictory, conflicted subjectivity, and those that
conceptualize postmodernity via a totalizing dialectical model as an
overarching global, political-economic, historical reality or periodizing
concept--remain significant. They are the differences that make a
difference in this debate, marking a key theoretical dividing line.
- Slavoj Zizek discusses the implications of the way this
dividing line is usually presented in contemporary theory. In a defense of
dialectical totalization against the notions of dissemination and
radically irreconcilable fragmentation that prevail in postmodern theory,
Zizek claims that the very form of the opposition as posed in the question
"gives predominance to the second term of the alternative" because it
"silently assumes that every attempt at rational totalization is in
advance doomed to failure" (For They 99). But this
characterization misrepresents the Hegelian understanding of a rational
totality, he writes, in that "the very impetus of the 'dialectical
progress'" has to do with "the possibility of 'making a system' out of the
very series of failed totalizations, to enchain them in a
rational way, to discern the strange 'logic' that regulates the process by
means of which the breakdown of a totalization itself begets another
totalization" (99). He goes on to make a similar argument with regard to
the Marxist notion of the class struggle, which is widely criticized by
postmodernists as "the 'totalizing' moment of society, its structuring
principle,... a kind of ultimate guarantee authorizing us to grasp society
as a rational totality" (100). Such characterizations, Zizek argues,
overlook "the ultimate paradox of the notion of 'class struggle,'" which
is that
society is "held together" by the very antagonism, split, that forever
prevents its closure in a harmonious, transparent, rational Whole--by the
very impediment that undermines every rational totalization. Although
"class struggle" is nowhere directly given as a positive entity, it none
the less functions, in its very absence, as the point of
reference enabling us to locate every social phenomenon not by relating it
to class struggle as its ultimate meaning ("transcendental signified") but
by conceiving it as an(other) attempt to conceal and "patch up" the rift
of the class struggle, to efface its traces--what we have here is the
typical structural-dialectical paradox of an effect which exists only
in order to efface the causes of its existence; of an effect which in
a way "resists" its own cause. (100)
- Here Zizek, like Jameson, rebuts condemnations of the
maligned "closed, totalized system," claiming that Hegelian and Marxist
dialectical theory never aimed at total closure in the first place and
reasserting its methodological value in the face of postmodern criticisms
by arguing that those criticisms are based on a generalized and mistaken
conception of Hegelian and Marxist thinking in terms of absolute, total,
and unified systems. In other words, even Hegel knew that Absolute
Spirit's destiny of perfect, static self-contemplation was always already
rendered impossible by the ineluctable necessity of movement, and, as
Zizek writes, even Marx understood that the "'normal' state of capitalism
is the permanent revolutionizing of its own conditions of existence," even
though he sometimes proceeded "as if he [did] not know it, by
describing the very passage from capitalism to socialism in terms of...
vulgar evolutionist dialectics" (Sublime 52-53). While he
does defend the dialectical tradition, Zizek does not simply
revert to a "vulgar" Marxism (although Jameson has recently suggested that
such a move might in fact be called for in the post-Cold War era[5]). I develop a more thorough discussion of
his work below.
- Returning now to the issues at stake in the postmodernism
debate, I find persuasive the efforts of Jameson and Zizek to link them to
a dialectical tradition that, according to their arguments, has not been
"made obsolete" by the advent of postmodern theory. The concerns of this
latter discourse--from problems of representation and language to concerns
with history, subjectivity, aesthetics, and politics--have been and
continue to be central concerns of Marxist theory, notably in the work of
the critical theorists of the Frankfurt School. Thus, just as the
postmodernism question--even after all the pages devoted to it over the
past thirty years--still looms in the background of any contemporary
Marxist criticism, so too the questions of totality, capitalism, praxis,
telos, and the "properly political" must be brought to bear on any
postmodern theory and criticism that avoids such topics.
- As for the term postmodernism itself, it has
taken on multiple meanings in its various incarnations and has provoked
numerous attacks and debates. The semantic widening that has occurred as
the term has appeared in more and more discursive fields over the course
of its popularization should not, however, according to Hebdige, be taken
as reason to dismiss it as meaningless gibberish. On the contrary,
following Raymond Williams's reasoning in Keywords, he
suggests that "the more complexly nuanced a word is, the more likely it is
to have formed the focus for historically significant debates, to have
occupied a semantic ground in which something precious and important was
felt to be embedded" (182).
- As nonacademic writers and traditional humanist scholars
have made forays into this semantic ground, the assaults against the
concept of postmodernism have taken a variety of forms, including claims
that the term has no clear definition, that it's a faddish sign of
changing academic fashion or an irrelevant topic for elites to ponder and
debate in coded jargon, and especially recently, that the arguments
surrounding the term have run their course and deserve to die out quietly.
Yet each of these claims holds whatever degree of validity it may retain
only to the extent that it implicitly accepts to some degree from the
start the very kind of immanent, nominalist epistemology that is alleged
to be the hallmark of postmodernism, an epistemology according to which
the Jamesonian thesis--that postmodernity names the current historical
totality of our actual global political economy (even if an exhaustive
catalog of its empirical features remains properly impossible and if a
selective description of such features would necessarily reveal
contradictions)--is bracketed from the start. That is, it is possible to
dismiss the concept of postmodernism as a "mere" fad only within an
epistemological context that assumes that such fads constitute nothing
more than elements of a linguistic game played by the academic "discourse
community" and that they have relevance only to the extent that they, for
example, provide fodder for conversations, presentations, and publications
without ever "touching ground." In this sense, conservative intellectuals
who call for a return to essential Western values, the great classics,
moral authority, and foundational principles and who simultaneously
dismiss theories of postmodernism out of hand as fashionably relativistic
nihilism are trying to have it both ways: they want foundationalism, but
they want to insist at the same time that in the case of the concept of
postmodernism, there is no foundation, as if with a vigorous enough
rhetorical flourish they could make it--and what it signifies--disappear.
- In other words, there is a call to a reflection model of
language in the conservative position, yet the idea that the sign
postmodernism might refer to or reflect an actual "reality" is
dismissed (and therefore the sign is deemed meaningless). Of course, one
of the key features of postmodern theory--insofar as its lineage includes
structuralist linguistics and the application of the linguistic model
across the full range of theoretical discourse and cultural practices (and
even the critique of the binary coding of this model in the
poststructuralist moment)--is its questioning of the strict distinction
between the "real world" and (linguistic) representation. As Derrida put
it, "From the moment there is meaning there are nothing but signs" (50).
But then at another level, mimesis reintroduces itself because such a
theory may be held to "reflect" a certain virtualization,
spectacularization, and intensified semioticization of the "real world"
itself in the era of mass media and computerization and of the movement of
scientific research toward what Lyotard calls "postmodern science"
(53-60).[6]
- In any case, the conservative criticism wants to refuse
both postmodern theory itself and the possibility that the theory may
indicate that something "really has changed" about the world conceived and
described in the discourses of modernity. Any tendencies in intellectual
and cultural discourse that have emphasized the role of language and
cultural forms in constructing social reality are therefore deemed suspect
and potentially dangerous in that they allegedly put the cart of language
and culture before the horse of the reality they reflect. Examples would
include the aesthetic and cultural politics of the modernist avant-garde,
who understood their work to be ahead of its time and who emphasized the
autonomy of art and its consequent role in shaping rather than reflecting
social reality; the Nietzschean-Heideggerian-Derridean philosophical
lineage that emphasizes language as a kind of inescapable horizon
circumscribing reality, history, experience, and consciousness; the
Althusserian structuralist-Marxist emphasis on "ideological state
apparatuses" as determinants of subjectivity; the propensity within
literary criticism after the rise of semiotic theory to see signs
everywhere, even where--the conservative critic would want to say--we used
to see things; and the Lacanian psychoanalytic focus on the linguistic
structure of the unconscious and the determining role of language in the
formation of subjectivity. All of these very different critical approaches
would be considered a departure from "common sense" realism and
traditional foundational premises.
- The reflection or mimetic model of language and
representation is also, however, a simplified version of a certain line of
anti-poststructuralist Marxist critique. That is, as a counter to the
tendency in poststructuralism to insist on the omnipresence of textuality,
a traditional Marxist theoretical response insists on the determination of
the cultural superstructure in the last instance by the economic base
even if that "last instance" functions as a limit that is never actually
reached and even if such determinations are mediated in multiple complex
ways. So a kind of affinity can be seen between conservative and Marxist
arguments against extreme versions of poststructuralism, but that shared
criticism is where the similarity generally ends. The conservative
argument is usually made in the name of an idealized conception of
intellectual history as "great men who wrote great books." Thus the
critical-materialist dimension of Marxism is at odds with it. But there is
a contending discourse, to which I have already referred, that offers a
dialectical critical theory also strictly at odds with extreme versions of
postmodern theory yet at the same time apparently comfortably
"post"-Marxist and therefore (more of) a puzzle (than humanist liberalism
or conservatism) for anyone claiming allegiance to traditional or "vulgar"
Marxist materialism.
Zizek, Defender of the Dialectic
- Among the most celebrated academic celebrities of the nineties,
Slavoj Zizek is a prolific and authoritative writer who explains
philosophical and psychoanalytic concepts through references to popular
culture, jokes, and political ideologies. His work has done much to
advance a psychoanalytic theory of ideology, offering a combined
Lacanian-Hegelian model as a counter to both traditional Marxist ideology
critique and more recent poststructuralist discourse analysis. His style
is often breezy, associative, enjoyable, and hyperbolic, to the extent
that it is not until one finishes reading that one begins to feel that he
has been repeating the same idea throughout the various short segments of
the text. This observation is not meant to imply that he is literally
repeating himself but to suggest that the form of his arguments often
appears the same even if the content shifts restlessly. From a certain
distance, he appears to be an entertainer who can quickly and cleverly
make Moebius strips out of every kind of material he encounters.
Nonetheless, much of his work seems to capture perfectly the workings of
ideology in our "post-ideological" times.
- To take one example, in The Sublime Object of
Ideology Zizek revisits Pascal's argument about the real
effectivity of material practice, regardless of what one takes to be one's
subjective beliefs (33-40). The simplified version of Pascal's approach to
this topic is, "Kneel, and you will believe." In other words, the
ritualized practice of regulated bodily movements in particular religious
settings, accompanied by specific physical sensations over time in a
regular pattern, is enough to "induce" belief in a doubter. Zizek is
careful to stress, however, the distinction between this materialism of
"custom" and the simplistic concept of brainwashing or "insipid
behaviorist wisdom ('the content of your belief is conditioned by your
factual behavior')" (40), a distinction based on "the paradoxical status
of a belief before belief":
By following a custom, the subject believes without knowing it, so that
the final conversion is merely a formal act by means of which we recognize
what we have already believed. In other words, what the behaviorist
reading of Pascalian "custom" misses is the crucial fact that the external
custom is always a material support for the subject's unconscious. (40)
- Zizek applies this argument about the "automatism of the
signifier" to a variety of homologous situations, such as the spinning of
Tibetan prayer wheels and the practice in some cultures of hiring
"weepers" to grieve on one's behalf. He draws from these various examples
the general lesson that external, material factors play an important
though paradoxical role in producing, which is to say enabling
retrospective recognition of, what are usually taken to be internal,
spiritual-ideological states. This process thus demonstrates "the
objectivity of belief": the ritualized behavior "does the believing" for
the doubter and induces/allows acknowledgment of "real" belief; the
spinning wheels carrying written prayers effectively "do the praying" for
whoever spins them; the hired mourners "do the grieving" for the relative
of the deceased. As further examples, Zizek cites Lacan's comments on the
Chorus in Greek tragedy, which does "our duty of compassion for the
heroes" even if we are "just drowsily watching the show," as well as the
familiar current example of canned laughter and applause on the
soundtracks of television shows, sounds that perform the same function as
the classical Chorus: "the Other--embodied in the television set--is
relieving us even of our duty to laugh--is laughing instead of us" (35).
- Developing this idea in specifically Marxist terms, Zizek
emphasizes the point that commodity fetishism is a property not of
consciousness but of objective behavior and that belief in the fetish is
always ascribed to a "subject presumed to believe." Thus in their actual
socioeconomic behavior, in their everyday activity, people fetishize
commodities, even though consciously, they are perfectly aware that the
"relations between things" mask "relations between people" ("Supposed"
41). In such a context, Zizek points out, the task for theory is not to
"demonstrate how the original human belief was transposed onto things"; on
the contrary, "displacement is original and constitutive" ("Supposed" 41).
No one consciously acknowledges that he or she believes in the magical
properties of commodities; rather, this belief is attributed always to an
Other, in this case, to the uncritical consumer who is duped by the
messages of advertising, ignorantly seeking happiness through the
consumption of commodities:
There are some beliefs, the most fundamental ones, which are from the very
outset "decentered," beliefs of the Other; the phenomenon of the "subject
supposed to believe" is thus universal and structurally necessary.... All
concrete versions of this "subject supposed to believe" (from the small
kids for whose sake their parents pretend to believe in Santa Claus to the
"ordinary working people" for whose sake communist intellectuals pretend
to believe in socialism) are stand-ins for the big Other. So the answer to
the conservative platitude according to which every honest man has a
profound need to believe in something is that every honest man has a
profound need to find another subject who would believe in his place.
("Supposed" 41-42)
After summarizing this argument about the psychological displacement of
belief that characterizes the subject's relation to commodities in
capitalist society, Zizek specifies the appropriate Marxist response,
which is not to perform a kind of primary-level ideology critique, since
the bourgeois subject is already consciously critical:
What the fetish objectivizes is "my true belief," the way things "truly
seem to me," although I never effectively experience them this way.... So
when a critical Marxist encounters a bourgeois subject immersed in
commodity fetishism, the Marxist's reproach to him is not "Commodity may
seem to you a magical object endowed with special powers, but it really is
just a reified expression of relations between people"; the actual
Marxist's reproach is rather "You may think that the commodity appears to
you as a simple embodiment of social relations (that, for example, money
is just a kind of voucher entitling you to a part of the social product),
but this is not how things really seem to you--in your social
reality, by means of your participation in social exchange, you bear
witness to the uncanny fact that a commodity really appears to you as a
magical object endowed with special powers." ("Supposed" 54)
In other words, bourgeois subjects think they see through the veil of the
commodity form and rest comfortably in that critical knowledge of
socioeconomic relations; but in reality, they behave as if they believe
differently from what they know, and their relation to commodities is the
objective illustration of this disavowed belief.
- This line of reasoning, then, locates ideology not in
consciousness but in real activity. Zizek cites the formula for
contemporary cynical ideology proposed in Peter Sloterdijk's
Critique of Cynical Reason: as opposed to the traditional
Marxist notion, according to which people are "duped" into believing the
ruling ideology and thus "do not know what they are doing" when they
effectively participate in their own subjugation, contemporary popular
cynicism forces us to consider the notion of an "enlightened false
consciousness" whereby "they know very well what they are doing, but
still, they are doing it" (Sublime 29).
- Like most analyses of subjectivity in contemporary
theory, this version disrupts radically the notion of a fully self-present
subject: the grain of material practice in time is always already altering
all ideological symbolization. To use Zizek's Lacanian language: the
irreducible "hard kernel" of the Real remains unassimilated into the
Symbolic order. One can, for example, have a self-conception as an ironic,
critical viewer who watches TV comedies as kitsch or as the detritus of
the culture industry, but according to Zizek's version of externalized
ideology, as long as one sits and watches--whether laughing idiotically or
making ironic, cynical comments--objectively, one is doing one's duty to
"enjoy the show." This notion has significant implications for theories of
both ideology and subjectivity. For example, the determining effect of
objective activity regardless of subjective intention can be read as
another way of stating the existentialist slogan that there is no "dress
rehearsal" for life: at each moment actions are final and decisive, even
if one believes oneself to be, for example, merely "performing a role"
temporarily before returning to some other "real life." That real life is
being determined at each instant by numerous material factors in the face
of which a concept like "personal choice" loses the certainty of its
suggestion of direct action in pursuit of clearly understood interests.
- This Lacanian "hard kernel" that appears prominently in
Zizek's work can have varying political valences. Its value for radical
politics derives from its affirmation of the Lacanian notion of the
inherent lack enabling subjectivity: the subject is constituted through,
yet simultaneously split by, the object-cause of desire such that the "it"
is always already there before the "I" can be recognized. This focus on
that which cannot be made consciously transparent to the subject through
linguistic symbolization counters a prevailing current of contemporary
mainstream U.S. culture that denies or derides the unconscious as an
invention of psychoanalysis in the same way that it denies or derides
class struggle as an invention of Marxism, both treated as entirely
discredited projects. The idea that rational linguistic processes can
never achieve transparency and that subjects are unable to know fully
their own motivations is corrosive to the basic assumptions of liberalism.
If rational discourse is subtended by an unassimilable, extradiscursive
Real, then the model of liberal politics--free, rational subjects
representing their interests through transparent communication in an
effort to achieve consensus--is called into question. "Freedom,"
"rationality," and "transparency" are shown to be ideological fictions
draped over the Real, which is never fully covered by them. Such a model
poses problems for, among other projects, the Habermasian
social-democratic ideal of rational intersubjective communication as well
as the American liberal neopragmatism promoted by Richard Rorty.[7]
- For all the ground it gains in destabilizing liberal
politics, the "hard kernel of the Real" also raises problems for radical
politics. To the extent that it can be understood as a zone of absolute,
prediscursive otherness beyond criticism, the Real can function as a
naturalized, ahistorical alibi that assures in advance the failure of
systemic critique and future-oriented political projects by fetishizing
the moment at which we must throw up our hands and admit ignorance and the
failure of representation. This insistence on the Real as radically
foreclosed from symbolization thus effectively serves existing hegemonic
relations by reinforcing the lines of inclusion and exclusion that
determine the relative power accorded to various subject positions as
inevitable effects of an invariant law of the Real. This is essentially
Judith Butler's critique of Zizek along feminist-poststructuralist
lines.[8]
- Another common criticism of Zizek holds that he
ultimately takes no position on the ideological issues he addresses. The
problem is related to that Moebius strip quality mentioned above: Zizek
consistently performs stunning critical analyses, but the question of
where they are supposed to lead is not always answered, especially in
The Sublime Object of Ideology, his first book published in
English. Indeed, at the 1999 MLA convention, Teresa Ebert criticized Zizek
from a strictly traditional Marxist standpoint, characterizing him as a
contemporary cynic trapped in the dead-end of "enlightened false
consciousness," and arguing that despite his self-presentation as a critic
who exposes the workings of contemporary popular-cynical ideology, Zizek
himself assumes what amounts to a meta-cynical posture that does not free
him from the charge of cynicism.
- Perhaps as a result of criticisms that his work avoids
adopting clear and consistent political stances, Zizek has made some of
his "ideological" positions more explicit in his recent writing.[9] These recent essays directly address
contemporary ideological issues, undermining critical comments such as the
following by Sean Homer:
His work never really moves to that second moment, whereby a consideration
of what ideology returns to us may facilitate the formulation of
oppositional ideologies and the space of politics proper. I always remain
unclear, for example, what Zizek is actually arguing for. Moreover, for
Zizek, this is not really a legitimate question; it is somehow to miss the
point. (par. 12)
In a similar gesture, Denise Gigante has made this characterization of
Zizek's work as apolitical or "undecidable" the central point of her
recent article on him: "But where Zizek is unique, and where he makes his
radical break with other literary theorists who take up a position, any
position at all that pretends to some notional content, is the fact that
he fundamentally has no position" (153).
- This conception of Zizek as a political cipher is perhaps
understandable on a first reading of a text like Looking Awry
or even The Sublime Object of Ideology and on a hasty
categorization of him as a "poststructuralist psychoanalytic theorist" (a
categorization that would require considerable elaboration). But in light
of careful analysis of a wide selection of his writings, it would be
difficult to insist on Zizek's political inscrutability. On the contrary,
his work evinces a general ideological commitment to a radical democracy
that is critical of both the globalizing capitalism of the present and the
bureaucratic state socialism of the recent past. Thus, he advocates an
(admittedly somewhat nebulous) "third way" for the future while
acknowledging the need for nation-states in the present as a counter both
to the increasing transnationalism of capital and to the dialectically
co-determined phenomenon of increasing ethnic and religious
"fundamentalist" violence and racism. While Zizek does not frequently
perform detailed analysis of specific policy issues, he does write
consistently from within the broad ideological framework I have described
above--contrary to the effort of Gigante to build an entire argument on
the premise that Zizek's "subjective transparency is precisely his point"
(154) and of Homer to chastise him for failing to draw connections between
his critical writing and the political sphere. Indeed, the following
passage provides a clear statement of his ideas about at least one major
topic of recent political philosophy, the "civil society" of late
capitalism:
People have this ethics of the bad state and good civic, independent
structures. But sorry, in Slovenia I am for the state and against civil
society! In Slovenia, civil society is equal to the right-wingers. In
America, after the Oklahoma bombing, they suddenly discovered that there
are hundreds of thousands of jerks. Civil society is not this nice social
movement but a network of moral majority conservatives and nationalist
pressure groups, against abortion, for religious education in schools: a
real pressure from below. ("Japan," par. 24)
- As for his stance with respect to political economy, it
is clear that a major aim of Zizek's work is a critique of capitalism in
an effort to contribute to the building of an anti-capitalist agenda in
the realm of the political, where struggles for hegemony are constantly
engaged and renewed. Following the general thrust of post-Gramscian
Marxism, he stresses that this hegemonizing process of "winning consent"
is always at work, even at the supposedly objective level of the economy.
Thus he argues, for example, that warnings from financial experts about
the dangers of certain economic reform measures, even when such warnings
are backed up by citations of crises "caused" by similar policies in other
situations, should not be understood as neutral descriptions of
"objective" economic causality:
The fact that, if one does not obey the limits set by Capital, a crisis
"really follows," in no way "proves" that the necessity of these limits is
an objective necessity of economic life. It should rather be conceived as
proof of the privileged position Capital holds in the economic and
political struggle, as in the situation where a stronger partner
threatens that if you do X, you will be punished by Y, and then, upon your
doing X, Y effectively ensues. ("Multiculturalism" 35)
While this is a recent and fairly direct comment on the dynamics of
multinational capitalist economic policy, his work has always exhibited an
engagement with Marxist theory and has always been implicitly and often
explicitly grounded in the project of a critique of capitalist social
relations and ideology, especially as these are connected with questions
of subjectivity. Numerous other examples could be cited in addition to the
two passages above, each a rebuke to the attempt to represent Zizek as an
apolitical ironist, resistant "to being born into any critical stance,"
as Gigante characterizes him (160).
- In any case, many of Zizek's arguments and concepts seem
"intuitively" accurate in the contemporary world: representation does
fail; evil does show itself; rational discourse does break down;
motivations for behavior are not always explicable; ideology does seem to
function through enjoyment at some level; ironic distance and cynicism,
far from being subversive, do seem to be built into hegemonic discourse
today. The relevance of these issues can be seen in recent episodes of
violence in U.S. schools. It is possible to string the shootings together
and interpret their meaning, drawing rational conclusions of various
ideological shadings: the events are a sign of the moral bankruptcy of our
secular society, an aftereffect of the permissive, anti-establishment
counterculture of the sixties, which has left young people without a
consistent moral code and ex-hippie adults with no authority to enforce
such a code if it did exist. Conversely, one can argue that the violence
is a sign of the growing alienation of youth in an increasingly
competitive late-capitalist socioeconomic system in which all value has
been translated into market value, a situation that sends parents to work
for more hours of the week and leaves children to be surrogate-parented by
television and other forms of commercial mass culture, which merely
replicate and augment the alienation of the adult world, cynically
positioning them solely as consumers representing market segments. Zizek's
work seems to suggest that neither the moralistic-conservative nor the
Marxist-radical analysis (nor even the liberal reformer's argument for gun
control and educational prevention programs) will ultimately touch the
"hard kernel of the Real" that emerges in all these cases of youth
violence. Indeed, notwithstanding broad characterizations of contemporary
theory as "antimetaphysical," something like a theological conception of
primal evil seems to be operating here and in work by theorists like
Baudrillard, who argues in The Transparency of Evil that all
the effort at eliminating evil from contemporary discourse (the various
constructive engagement policies, win-win scenarios, conflict resolution
programs, self-esteem workshops, and up-with-people organizations) cannot
eradicate it, even if that evil is hidden and denied, or more accurately,
is desymbolized:
The world is so full of positive feelings, naive sentimentality,
self-important rectitude and sycophancy that irony, mockery, and the
subjective energy of evil are always in the weaker position. At
this rate every last negative sentiment will soon be forced into a
clandestine existence. (107-08)
Another passage in the same text seems to forecast the logic of the
school-violence outbursts of recent years:
In a society which seeks--by prophylactic measures, by annihilating its
own natural referents, by whitewashing violence, by exterminating all
germs and all of the accursed share, by performing cosmetic surgery on the
negative--to concern itself solely with quantified management and with the
discourse of the Good, in a society where it is no longer possible to
speak of Evil, Evil has metamorphosed into all the viral and terroristic
forms that obsess us. (81)
- Thus evil erupts in any number of instances of the return
of the repressed, among which the school shootings would no doubt be
deemed exemplary, [10] as would the
plot of their precursor text, Michael Lehmann's film Heathers
(1989), a dark comedy about the class structure of a "typical" suburban
high school (an especially relevant reference in light of media reports
about the clique-resentment that at least in part fueled the April 1999
killings at a "typical" suburban high school in Colorado). In this film
the narrator, who at first tries to become accepted by the dominant group
of girls (all named Heather), is eventually drawn by her sociopathic
boyfriend into unknowingly helping him murder their popular-girl and
jock-boy classmates, passing off the incidents as suicides, an explanation
that the adults and other students are exceedingly willing to accept. The
point for Baudrillard, following Bataille, is that the "accursed share"
cannot be extricated from any economy: the "bad subject" may eventually
try to blow up the school during the pep rally. This analysis essentially
repeats a formula that Zizek frequently quotes from Lacan's Third Seminar,
Les Psychoses: "What is refused in the Symbolic order returns
in the Real."
- But we should not let this "theological" reading of
contemporary evil stand without further elaboration since neither Zizek
nor Baudrillard grounds his comments in Christian theology or calls for a
stricter adherence to traditional moral codes as a "solution." For Zizek
this would be no solution at all, since morality operates in Symbolic
reality while the particular kind of evil that he diagnoses in, for
example, racist violence, skinhead beatings, and school shootings has
roots in the non-symbolized Real of jouissance.
Simulacrum, Superego, Lacanian Ethics, and the Problem of Evil
- According to Zizek, theorists of postmodern society who make much
of the usurpation of the Real by the simulacrum either long nostalgically
for the lost distinction between them or announce the final overcoming of
the "metaphysical obsession with authentic Being," or both (he mentions
Paul Virilio and Gianni Vattimo, and we might add Baudrillard to the
list). In either case they "miss the distinction between simulacrum and
appearance":
What gets lost in today's plague of simulations is not the firm, true,
nonsimulated Real, but appearance itself. To put it in Lacanian
terms: the simulacrum is imaginary (illusion), while appearance is
symbolic (fiction); when the specific dimension of symbolic appearance
starts to disintegrate, imaginary and real become more and more
indistinguishable.... And, in sociopolitical terms, this domain of
appearance (that is, symbolic fiction) is none other than that of
politics.... The old conservative motto of keeping up appearances thus
today obtains a new twist:... [it] stands for the effort to save the
properly political space. ("Leftist" 995-96)
- Making the same argument about a slightly different
version of this problem, Zizek writes that the standard reading of
"outbursts of 'irrational' violence" in the postmodern "society of the
spectacle" is that "our perception of reality is mediated by aestheticized
media manipulations to such an extent that it is no longer possible for us
to distinguish reality from its media image" (Metastases 75).
Violent outbursts in this context are thus seen as "desperate attempts to
draw a distinction between fiction and reality... [and] to dispel the
cobweb of the aestheticized pseudo-reality" (75). Again with reference to
the Lacanian triad of Imaginary-Symbolic-Real, Zizek argues that this
analysis is "right for the wrong reasons":
What is missing from it is the crucial distinction between imaginary order
and symbolic fiction.
The problem of contemporary media resides not in their enticing us to
confound fiction with reality but, rather, in their "hyperrealist"
character by means of which they saturate the void that keeps open the
space for symbolic fiction. (75)
A society of proliferating, promiscuous images is thus not overly
fictionalized but is, on the contrary, not "fictionalized" enough in the
sense that the basis for making valid statements, the structure
guaranteeing intersubjective communication, the order permitting shared
narratives and, to use Jameson's term, "cognitive mapping"[11]--in short, the realm of the Symbolic--is
short-circuited by an incessant flow of images, which solicit not analysis
and the powers of thought but rather nothing more than blank, unreflective
enjoyment.
- The kind of subjectivity that corresponds to this
hyperreal, spectacularized society without a stable Symbolic order is what
Zizek calls in Looking Awry the "pathological narcissist"
(102). That is, following the predominance of the "'autonomous' individual
of the Protestant ethic" and the "heteronomous 'organization man'" who
finds satisfaction through "the feeling of loyalty to the group"--the two
models of subjectivity corresponding to previous stages of capitalist
society--today's media-spectacle-consumer society is marked by the rise of
the "pathological narcissist," a subjective structure that breaks with the
"underlying frame of the ego-ideal common to the first two forms" (102).
The first two forms involved inverted versions of each other: one either
strove to remain true to oneself (that is, to a "paternal ego-ideal") or
looked at oneself "through the eyes of the group," which functioned as an
"externalized" ego-ideal, and sought "to merit its love and esteem" (102).
With the stage of the "pathological narcissist," however, the ego-ideal
itself is dissolved:
Instead of the integration of a symbolic law, we have a multitude
of rules to follow--rules of accommodation telling us "how to
succeed." The narcissistic subject knows only the "rules of the (social)
game" enabling him to manipulate others; social relations constitute for
him a playing field in which he assumes "roles," not proper symbolic
mandates; he stays clear of any kind of binding commitment that would
imply a proper symbolic identification. He is a radical
conformist who paradoxically experiences himself as an
outlaw. (102)
Thus the "permissive" society of the last decades of the twentieth
century, marked by the often-noted "decline of paternal authority," turns
out not to be more liberating than earlier social formations after all; in
fact, Zizek writes, "this disintegration of the ego-ideal entails the
installation of a 'maternal' superego that does not prohibit enjoyment
but, on the contrary, imposes it and punishes 'social failure' in a far
more cruel and severe way, through an unbearable and self-destructive
anxiety" (103).
- While its generalized form may be more recent, the
effects of this overbearing presence of the maternal superego are already
evident in Orson Welles's Citizen Kane (1941).[12] The film offers viewers a fairly
simple "psychological" reading of the title character's dying utterance,
"Rosebud": we learn at the end of the narrative that this was the name of
Kane's childhood sled; thus we surmise that Kane's saying the word as he
dies indicates his nostalgic longing for his idyllic Colorado childhood.
The word evokes the period before Kane was separated from his parents--at a
time when he was not yet mature enough (still a "rosebud") to make
decisions for himself--and was inserted into a position of wealth and power
that he never sought and in which he could not, after all, find true
happiness.
But this reading
overlooks the fact that it is Kane's mother who initiates the tragic
progression of her son's future through her desire that Charles should
have a "better life" than was possible in their rural home. It also
overlooks the related fact that she does so over the impotent objections
of Kane's ineffectual father, a man who is without power because he is
without property: the deed to the mine that has become the source of the
family's sudden wealth belongs to Mrs. Kane alone.
- Kane's acts of youthful rebellion against his despised
guardian-father Thatcher, which include transgressions that get him
expelled from various elite colleges, and his decision to enter adult
public life as the publisher of a sensationalistic, populist,
anti-big-business newspaper because running a newspaper might be "fun," as
he tells Thatcher, appear at first to be attempts to break free of the
restrictive "law of the father" embodied in the stern and humorless
banker, who predictably disapproves of Kane's activities and decisions.
But Thatcher is merely a substitute-father put in place to enact the
desire of Kane's mother that Charles should grow up to be someone
important, a situation that Kane never shows any awareness of in his
defiance. As Kane's friend Jed Leland, thinking back on their
relationship, comments about Kane, "He loved Charlie Kane, of course, very
dearly; and his mother--I guess he always loved her." Kane's explicit
rebellion, then, is directed against the world of sober responsibility as
law-of-the-father and thus takes the form of his "enjoying himself,"
"having fun," and "championing the cause of the common man," behavior that
he experiences as transgressive but that actually involves his acting out
the paradoxical injunction to enjoy imposed by the maternal superego.
- As for Kane's fight for "the common man," it is ambiguous
at best and seems to be motivated initially by the enjoyment that he
derives from defying Thatcher and promoting causes antithetical to his
interests. His "convictions" are sustained thereafter by his enjoyment of
the support and adulation of friends and voters during his political
campaign. Significantly, it is just when it appears inevitable, according
to polls, that Kane will win the election and become governor--that is,
just when he will have to make good on his attested convictions and assume
the symbolic position of paternal authority as embodiment of Law--that he
initiates an extramarital affair, which, when exposed, leads to his defeat
on election day. This pathological pattern is continued later in the
film as he begins wasting money by making wildly irrational
expenditures on useless objects to fill his "fantasy palace," Xanadu,
violating the paternal laws of utility and economy and evading the
"reality principle": he remains trapped in a cycle of compulsive
repetition on a narcissistic quest for enjoyment that can never be
achieved precisely because it is demanded by the maternal superego, which
determines his actions despite his properly egotistical claims that only
he himself decides what he will do.
- On the night when he first meets his mistress and second
wife Susan Alexander while on the way to a warehouse where his deceased
mother's possessions are stored, Kane learns that Alexander's mother
always wanted Susan to be an opera singer. As if by command, he
immediately asks her to sing for him that evening and soon begins the
process of training her for an opera career, fulfilling the desire of her
mother regardless of Susan's own desire and thereby taking on the role
that Thatcher played for Kane himself as a youth. As both Kane's and
Susan's misery demonstrate, however, avoiding the law of the father by
fulfilling the desire of the mother is hardly an advisable course of
action.[13] As Leland remarks, directly
contradicting the affected ethical resolution of Kane's "declaration of
principles," which Kane signs with a flourish in front of Leland and
publishes in his newspaper early in the film, Kane "never believed in
anything except Charlie Kane; he never had a conviction except Charlie
Kane in his life"--precisely the definition of the "pathological
narcissist." This subjective structure is figured near the end of the film
in the famous shot of Kane walking past a mirrored mirror, producing a
brief infinite regression of images of himself. Inasmuch as his "self"
of infinite narcissistic images and his own private (blocked) enjoyment
mark the limits of his "care," Kane has remained under the command of the
maternal superego and never acceded to symbolic law.
- Zizek specifies this crucial opposition between symbolic
law and superego explicitly in terms of the movement from permission to
obligation, from possibility based on clearly defined universal
prohibition to necessity based on radical contingency. Paradoxically, in
the absence of prohibition, where one might expect the free flow of
libidinal energy, superego intervenes to require what is already
permitted:
Law is the agency of prohibition which regulates the distribution of
enjoyment on the basis of a common, shared renunciation (the "symbolic
castration"), whereas superego marks a point at which permitted
enjoyment, freedom-to-enjoy, is reversed into obligation to
enjoy--which, one must add, is the most effective way to block access to
enjoyment. (For They 237)
- It is because of this obscene, harsh, punitive quality of
the superego that the subject can never settle accounts with it. There is
always more that can be sacrificed, Zizek explains, which is why Lacanian
psychoanalytic ethics is based explicitly on opposing the coercion of the
superego, in contrast to the ordinary association of superego with
"conscience" or the moral sense guiding ethical behavior:
Lacan's maxim of the ethics of psychoanalysis ("not to compromise one's
desire") is not to be confounded with the pressure of the
superego.... Lacan takes seriously and literally the Freudian "economical
paradox" of the superego--that is, the vicious cycle that characterizes
the superego: the more we submit ourselves to the superego imperative, the
greater its pressure, the more we feel guilty. According to Lacan, this
"feeling of guilt" is not a self-deception to be dispelled in the course
of the psychoanalytic cure--we really are guilty: superego draws
the energy of the pressure it exerts upon the subject from the fact that
the subject was not faithful to his desire, that he gave it up. Our
sacrificing to the superego, our paying tribute to it, only corroborates
our guilt. For that reason our debt to the superego is unredeemable: the
more we pay it off, the more we owe. (Metastases 67-68)
Indeed, Lacan's ethical imperative must be taken as explicitly opposed to
the concept of conventional morality with its focus on maximizing the
Good, which functions as the arbiter of all action, since this model
ultimately leads to a psychological paralysis arising from infinite
consideration of ramifications, a process that turns the subject into a
perpetual Hamlet, standing behind Claudius but unable to decide whether
killing him or not killing him would be the better option. The
interminable process of trying to decide which course of action leads to
the "greater Good" entails its own kind of choice (that is, to "compromise
one's desire" by default) with its own kind of psychic consequences for
the subject. Zizek explains this ethical-moral distinction through a
Greimasian semiotic square based on the four possible arrangements of the
positive and negative versions of these terms and the figures
corresponding to the four pairings--moral, ethical (Saint); immoral,
unethical (Scoundrel); immoral, ethical (Hero); and moral, unethical
(superego)--and endorses the Lacanian championing of Hero over superego
(Metastases 67).
- Zizek also anticipates the anxious objection that this
Lacanian ethical attitude is too radical in its practical implications: is
it reasonable to propose that everyone unrelentingly pursue his or her own
desire and renounce all other considerations? Don't "ordinary" people need
an "ethics of the 'common Good,'... despicable as it may appear in the
eyes of the suicidal heroic ethics advocated by Lacan?"
(Metastases 69). But he concludes that this concern--"What if
everyone were to do the same as me?"--is simply another way of introducing
the "pathological consideration of the consequences of our act in
reality" and therefore functions as a way of imposing superego
injunctions, restraints, and cycles of guilt through the insistence that
we renounce our desire precisely because it cannot be universalized (69).
- From these comments on the Lacanian ethics of desire,
Zizek moves, understandably, into a section on the unavoidable corollary
to such an ethics, that is, the problem of evil, which has prompted the
present discussion. Zizek identifies three kinds of evil, categorized
according to the Freudian scheme of Ego, Superego, and Id. Ego-Evil is the
most common kind: "behavior motivated by selfish calculation and greed";
Superego-Evil is the kind attributed to "fundamentalist fanatics," that
is, "Evil accomplished in the name of fanatical devotion to some
ideological ideal"; finally, there is Id-Evil, "structured and motivated
by the most elementary imbalance in the relationship between the
Ich and jouissance, by the tension between pleasure and
the foreign body of jouissance at the very heart of it"
(Metastases 70-71). In other words, Id-Evil involves a kind
of pure, irrational enjoyment in the evil act. The skinheads who beat up
foreigners because it "feels good" to do so, the white racists who killed
an African-American man by dragging him from a chain tied behind their
pickup truck because the mere presence of a black man "bothered" them, the
adolescents who committed the shooting sprees in U.S. schools over the past
several years: all of these cases involve "violence not grounded in
utilitarian or ideological reasons" ("Leftist" 998) but rather raw
outbreaks of the Real of jouissance:
The psychotic passage à l'acte is to be conceived of as a
desperate attempt of the subject to evict objet a from reality by
force, and thus gain access to reality. (The psychotic "loss of reality"
does not arise when something is missing in reality, but, on the contrary,
when there is too much of a Thing in reality.)
(Metastases 77)
- Of course, what is most disturbing about such instances
of the psychotic passage à l'acte is the often-reported
"desensitization" of the subject toward the violent acts that he performs.
The reports about the Columbine High School shooting incident, for
example, included witnesses' recollections of some details of the two
killers' comments as they walked around shooting their classmates. It was
reported that they were laughing and saying, "We've been wanting to do
this for years," and commenting to each other about how "cool" it looked
to see blood and pieces of victims' bodies "fly" when they shot them. This
last statement precisely illustrates Zizek's diagnosis of the breakdown of
the distinction between the Imaginary and the Real in a society marked by
the attenuation of the Symbolic: the Real, the actual spraying of blood,
is experienced as Imaginary, as a "cool" image or effect, a purely
aesthetic phenomenon, while the Symbolic identity of the victim (someone
with a name, a family, a "story," a network of intersubjective
connections) is not considered or recognized.
Violence, Evil, and Late Capitalism at the Movies
- Such cases of "desensitization" toward violence and
desymbolization of victims' identities are widespread in contemporary
film, as conservative politicians, desperate to locate in the culture
industry the "causes" of violent crime (while impeding legislative efforts
to curb easy access to guns), are quick to mention. But limited claims for
causality (bad movies, bad parenting, bad guns) begin within a positivist
framework that, as discussed above, misses the eruption of the Real in
these cases of Id-Evil and that fails to account for the socioeconomic,
historical context of multinational capitalism within which such eruptions
take place. Even broader claims for causality based on the notion of a
widespread "culture of death"--encompassing media violence, the prevalence
of guns, drug abuse, as well as legalized abortion, euthanasia, and other
indicators of an alleged rejection of belief in the "sanctity of human
life"--fail to address the ways in which the structural demands of
capitalism have contributed to the unwelcome social and cultural
transformations since the "good old days" (usually meaning anytime before
the 1960s).
- These criticisms, in both narrow and broad versions, are
underwritten by the belief that with the correct combination of policy
reforms to excise the diseased elements of the social body we might return
to the "normal" state of society, having eliminated its anomalous,
disruptive features. This belief, however, itself depends on ignoring the
dialectical logic of the symptom, which Zizek, following Lacan, reminds us
was "invented" by Marx:
Marx's great achievement was to demonstrate how all phenomena which appear
to everyday bourgeois consciousness as simple deviations, contingent
deformations and degenerations of the "normal" functioning of society
(economic crises, wars, and so on), and as such abolishable through
amelioration of the system, are necessary products of the system
itself--the points at which the "truth," the immanent antagonistic
character of the system, erupts. (Sublime 128)
Thus if many U.S. adolescents feel isolated and desperate, see no future for
themselves that they would want to occupy, feel no symbolic identification
with any entity beyond themselves (nation, community, family), resent
their "well-adjusted" peers, expect little from others or themselves, and
shift among affective states of manic euphoria, defensive denial, and
depressive anomie, and if some of these adolescents realize their abject
frustration in acts of violence, those acts are not to be understood as
anomalies that might be "fixed" with appropriate reform measures but
rather as symptomatic eruptions of the "truth" of the current capitalist
world system. In other words, the explanation for these violent outbursts
has more to do with what Zizek has assessed as the attenuation of the
Symbolic order under conditions of globalizing media-technology-consumer
capitalism and the concomitant rise of the "pathological narcissist" as a
dominant mode of subjectivity than with any isolated individual "causes"
upon which empirical studies may be (and will be) performed.
- Still, a brief examination of late-capitalist film
violence is worthwhile, not as a direct cause behind actual violent
incidents but as a symptom of rationalized systemic violence and also
(sometimes) as a critical representation of it. For examples of the
former, we need look no further than action-adventure genre films, as well
as the video games based on this genre, and their often-noted uncritical,
"gratuitous" violence, which may certainly be characterized as
"symptomatic" of late capitalism to the extent that it functions within
hyper-masculine fantasy scenarios.[14]
While such cultural products may encode a justifiable desire for an
alternative to the "managed society" of "soft" liberalism, that
alternative is usually figured in terms of a fascistic emphasis on law and
order brought about through the exercise of violent masculine power and
domination.
- But then other films present violent situations in ways
that challenge prevailing genre conventions and invite critical reflection
on the meaning of the violence depicted. Perhaps the most relevant case of
the latter in recent years is Quentin Tarantino's Pulp
Fiction (1994), especially the famous scene in which John
Travolta's working-man gangster character Vincent Vega, gesturing with his
gun, accidentally shoots the character Marvin in the face when the car
they are riding in goes over a bump. The incident is treated as an
irritating inconvenience, prompting arguments between Vincent and Samuel
Jackson's Jules Winnfield character over Vincent's carelessness, the
potential for being seen by cops, and the general disruption in the smooth
routine of their day. Cleaning the car and disposing of the body are
regarded as chores to be dealt with as efficiently as possible. In fact,
"The Wolf" (Harvey Keitel), a specialist who "fixes things," is called in
to manage the clean-up operation. He, like Jules and Vincent, wears a
black business suit.
- First, it should be noted that many features of the
film, including the business suits, combine to create what looks like an
allegory of contemporary capitalism: Vincent and Jules are, after all,
hit-men working for Ving Rhames's black-market entrepreneur character
Marsellus Wallace, and their sudden, unpredictable violence is the truth
of a system whose purpose is to rationalize and manage that violence and
its perpetual threat efficiently in order to ensure the continuation of
exchange and profit. The Wolf is a free-agent consultant called in when
business "difficulties" arise. The "postmodern" quality of the
representation of capitalism here is evident by contrast with earlier
generations of crime films, in which the criminal enterprise is justified
by reference to some ideological principle, such as "beating the system"
by sticking together in bonds of friendship and allegiance to the "old
neighborhood," as in William Wellman's Public Enemy (1931)
and Michael Curtiz's Angels with Dirty Faces (1938), or
maintaining the "old way of life" associated with family and ethnic
heritage, as in Francis Ford Coppola's Godfather trilogy
(1972, 1974, 1990).
- Pulp Fiction "reflects" the late capitalist
moment in that its "post-ideological" criminals have no commitment to
anything but getting their own "piece of the action": the performativity
of the system is its own justification; no metanarrative is needed for
ideological legitimation. Other features of the film are also consistent
with late capitalism and contrast with earlier crime genre films: the
structure of the criminal operation appears to be decentralized and
"flexible"; the dividing line between criminal and non-criminal is blurry
at best; the criminals maintain loose, diversified connections across a
wide range of social strata, covering the decentered space of greater Los
Angeles's urban sprawl; and the idea of an alternative way of life--what
might have appeared as the position of the "good citizen" in an earlier
crime story--can be figured only by reference to a possibility that is
never shown.
- This alternative possibility is raised hypothetically in
Jules and Vincent's conversations about miracles and the gangster life.
After he and Vincent are fired upon multiple times in a surprise attack
from across a room without being hurt--an experience that Jules interprets
as a miracle--Jules raises the idea of giving up "the life" to "walk the
earth" as a kind of modern-day religious mendicant. Dismissing Jules's
interpretation of what he considers a "freak occurrence," Vincent scoffs
and tells Jules that there is a name for people who do what he has
proposed: "they're called bums." A typical contemporary "pathological
narcissist," Vincent mocks the suggestion that he and Jules have
experienced a miracle. As a skeptical nominalist, he is living in what he
takes to be, for better or worse, the "best of all possible worlds" and
cannot accept even the possibility of singularity or transcendence or of a
utopian potential beyond "the life." Significantly, Vincent is killed on
his next job for Marsellus, after Jules has quit, and the fact that his
death has been shown out of chronological sequence earlier in the plot
adds dramatic impact to the conversation in which Jules decides to quit
and Vincent ridicules him. We know already as they leave the diner at the
end of the film what their respective fates are--or at least we know
Vincent's; we never learn what happens to Jules. That reference to the
alternative--the desire to "walk the earth," to live outside the paranoid
circuits of power without participating in rationalized violence and
exploitation--suggests the utopian (and non-representable) dimension of
the film: the continuation of Jules's story cannot be shown precisely
because it gestures beyond the limits of contemporary capitalist society.
Any actual content provided for this future story would restrict and
trivialize the utopian desire suggested by his speculations.
- Just as the violent incidents in Pulp
Fiction in the context of the film as a whole estrange the violence
of the "normal," smooth, everyday functioning of contemporary capitalism,
inviting critical reflection, so too the jarring suddenness of the
violence when Vincent shoots Marvin, and in other scenes (and in other
Tarantino films), disrupts the smooth operation of ordinary narrative film
form, in which climactic, redemptive violent moments are usually cued
through narrative suspense, music, editing, lighting, and other
techniques. The unexpected intrusion of violence into scenes of witty
hipster banter among likable characters forces us to confront these
characters as agents of the violent system in which they participate, even
when they do not intend to use violence, that is, even when someone like
Marvin is killed "accidentally" as opposed to someone who "had it coming."
- In other words, the ethical-political lesson is Zizekian:
actions speak louder than words; the material actuality of practice
overrides intention. Vincent cannot guarantee that the Real will not
intrude on his rationalized, mundane, and solipsistic Ego-Evil. His
participation in the criminal life would be justified from his perspective
in terms of self-interest: as a contemporary cynic, he would reason that
if the entire capitalist system is just a large-scale criminal racket,
then his work as a gangster is the only intelligent response--he might as
well enjoy the high life instead of working like a sucker to line the
pockets of the corporate bosses in the legitimate economy. At the
allegorical level, then, this reading suggests that smart, hip cynics like
Vincent are actually the dutiful foot soldiers of contemporary capitalism.
Justifying any action in terms of "enlightened" cynical reason, such a
person is, as Zizek puts it in another context, a "crook who tries to sell
as honesty the open admission of his crookedness," effectively functioning
as a "conformist who takes the mere existence of the given order as an
argument for it" ("Leftist" 1004-05).
- Two final and related points deserve to be made, via
Zizek, about Jules and Vincent and their relationship to the event that
only Jules takes to be a miracle. First, their difference in
interpretation perfectly exemplifies Zizek's argument about the strict
separation between belief and knowledge:
Belief can only thrive in the shadowy domain between outright falsity and
positive truth. The Jansenist notion of miracle bears witness to the fact
that they were fully aware of this paradox: an event which has the quality
of a miracle only in the eyes of the believer--to the commonsense eyes of
an infidel, it appears as a purely natural coincidence. ("Supposed" 44)
This precise relationship is enacted in the conversation in which Jules
and Vincent argue over their respective interpretations of the event: no
amount of convincing will cause the other to abandon his interpretation
because logical proofs and rhetorical appeals operate in the realm of
knowledge, which will not touch belief. As Zizek puts it, "the miracle is
inherently linked to the fact of belief--there is no neutral miracle to
convince cynical infidels" ("Supposed" 44).
- The other point is that this argument also takes place in
the somewhat different register of class consciousness and subjectivity.
Perhaps stretching the allegorical reading of the Jules and Vincent story
in Pulp Fiction to its limit, I would suggest that Jules's
"conversion" experience might as easily be read in Marxist as in religious
terms. (And for the reasons cited above, the Marxist reading is not
without justification.) Thus allegorically, if Vincent clings to his
egocentric and effectively neoconservative cynicism, Jules's experience of
the miracle amounts to his interpellation as a proletarian subject, or at
least (since his story ends after his testament of faith) to a
protopolitical baptism. This moment of divergence in the trajectories of
the stories of two (until then) similar characters illustrates what Zizek
identifies as the crucial importance of class consciousness as distinct
from objective class position in the class struggle:
From a truly radical Marxist perspective, although there is a link between
the working class as a social group and the proletariat as the position of
the militant fighting for universal Truth, this link is not a determining
causal connection, and the two levels are to be strictly distinguished. To
be proletarian involves assuming a certain subjective stance (of
class struggle destined to achieve redemption through revolution) that, in
principle, can occur to any individual; to put it in religious terms,
irrespective of his (good) works, any individual can be touched by grace
and interpellated as a proletarian subject. The limit that separates the
two opposed sides in the class struggle is thus not objective, not the
limit separating two positive social groups, but ultimately radically
subjective; it involves the position individuals assume towards the
Event of universal Truth. ("Leftist" 1003)
Thus a long line of conversion stories--from the sudden, terrible hailing
of Saul of Tarsus through the more gradual radicalization of American
literary proletarians like Tom Joad and Biff Loman (whose relationship to
his brother Happy, despite numerous differences in detail, including
especially the absence of cynicism in Death of a Salesman, is
nonetheless homologous with that of Jules to Vincent after the disputed
event)--become enmeshed in the sociohistorical narrative of the formation
of revolutionary subjectivity. Zizek's commentary explains, among other
things, how class traitors are possible, since the class struggle, as he
puts it,
mobilizes... not the division between two well-defined social groups but
the division, which runs "diagonally" to the social division in the Order
of Being, between those who recognize themselves in the call of the
Truth-Event, becoming its followers, and those who deny or ignore it.
("Leftist" 1003)
The impetus behind this recognition and conversion need not, of course, be
a brush with violent death, as in the case of Jules. In principle, the
negative motivation for conversion is available everywhere in capitalist
society. As for positive or utopian "calls to conversion," these can be
found in unexpected spaces occasionally wrested free from the demands of
the vast commerical strip mall of contemporary U.S. culture.
Conclusion: Zizek as Late Marxist
- The title of this essay may be read to imply a progression of the
type thesis, antithesis, synthesis. Such a progression is not my
intention. I certainly do not wish to give the impression that I take
Zizek's work to be the culminating synthesis of the problematic of Marxism
and postmodernism. Nonetheless, I do regard his work, which responds with
dialectical thoroughness (and with humor, and with perceptive references
to popular culture, and with brilliant on-the-run insights) to new
problems of ideology and subjectivity in late capitalism, as a valuable
critical contribution to the tradition of Marxist theory, despite Ebert's
(and others') criticisms characterizing him as a cynical "post-Marxist."
If anything, his explicit appropriation of Hegel would perhaps better
qualify him for the critical label "pre-Marxist." But even such a
half-serious appellation would fail to account for the variety of careful
analyses, explanations, and criticisms appearing throughout his work that
can be characterized only as Marxist without a prefix. Or, if a prefix is
needed, then Jameson's term late Marxist would perhaps actually
be the most accurate for Zizek's work.
- Jameson has the following to say about the term late
Marxism in his 1990 book of that title:
I find it helpful above all for a sharpening of the implication I
developed above: namely, that Marxism, like other cultural phenomena,
varies according to its socioeconomic context. There should be nothing
scandalous about the proposition that the Marxism required by Third World
countries will have different emphases from the one that speaks to already
receding socialism, let alone to the "advanced" countries of multinational
capitalism. (11)
Thus late Marxism's "big tent," according to this conception, would have
room for a revival of a Freudian-Marxist theory of ideology by way of
Lacan and Hegel in the socioeconomic context of defeated state socialisms
in the former Eastern bloc and in the context of a triumphal, expanding
multinational capitalism based in the "advanced" capitalist countries. If
this version of Marxism is among those "required" for critically
understanding the dynamics of capitalist society and culture in this
context, then it belongs alongside the other Marxisms speaking to other
contexts of the late-capitalist world system.
- The more narrow context for Zizek's project of a revived
psychoanalytic Marxism is, as he puts it in the abstract opposite the
title pages of books in the Wo Es War series that he edits, "the twin rule
of pragmatic-relativist New Sophists and New Age obscurantists" in
critical writing. Commenting more specifically on the state of theory and
criticism in the age of globalizing capitalism and dominant market
ideology, Zizek writes:
It is effectively as if, since the horizon of social imagination no longer
allows us to entertain the idea of an eventual demise of
capitalism--since, as we might put it, everybody silently accepts that
capitalism is here to stay--critical energy has found a
substitute outlet in fighting for cultural differences which leave the
basic homogeneity of the capitalist world-system intact.
("Multiculturalism" 46)
If we accept these descriptions of the socioeconomic and critical contexts
into which Zizek intervenes, then the revival of dialectical models of
criticism that are capable of addressing systemic problems at a level of
sufficient generality and of drawing connections between "local" objects
and the "totality" of their relations is indeed precisely what is needed.
In any case, efforts to purge or discredit Zizek from an assumed position
of orthodoxy are not especially helpful to the Marxist cause in either of
the above contexts.
- Marxist and Freudian theory are parallel and privileged
theoretical discourses, according to Zizek, in part because the
relationship of each to theory itself is one aspect of its domain of
inquiry. This contentious reflexivity makes error a structurally necessary
element of the theory, as opposed to the case of positivist sciences:
In both cases we are dealing with a field of knowledge that is
inherently antagonistic: errors are not simply external to the
true knowledge.... In Marxism, as in psychoanalysis, truth literally
emerges through error, which is why in both cases the struggle with
"revisionism" is an inherent part of the theory itself.... The "object" of
Marxism is society, yet "class struggle in theory" means that the ultimate
theme of Marxism is the "material force of ideas"--that is, the way
Marxism itself qua revolutionary theory transforms its object
(brings about the emergence of the revolutionary subject, etc.). This is
analogous to psychoanalysis, which is also not simply a theory of its
"object" (the unconscious) but a theory whose inherent mode of existence
involves the transformation of its object (via interpretation in the
psychoanalytic cure). (Metastases 181-82)
Each theory, in short, "acknowledges the short circuit between the
theoretical frame and an element within this frame: theory itself is a
moment of the totality that is its 'object'" (Metastases
182). Such a process, Zizek insists, is not to be confused with a
"comfortable evolutionary position," which, "from a safe distance," seeks
"to relativize every determinate form of knowledge"
(Metastases 182-83). On the contrary, each tradition is
characterized by what he calls a "thought that endeavors to grasp its own
limitation and dependence" even as it proceeds, and this perpetual
critical interrogation of its own "position of enunciation" enables
whatever claims to truth it may make: "Marxism and psychoanalysis are
'infallible' at the level of enunciated content, precisely insofar as
they continually question the very place from which they speak"
(Metastases 182-83).
- I cite these comments in order to defend Zizek's Marxist
credentials against charges of post-Marxist cynicism. But I also recognize
that his welding of Lacanian psychoanalysis onto Marxism is not seamless:
irreducible traditional antagonisms between the two discourses can easily
seem to disappear because of Zizek's deft handling of both. Nonetheless,
his writing offers fresh and cogent criticism of contemporary culture and
society and opens avenues for further critical reflection, as I hope the
preceding analyses have shown. His Marxism is "late" not in the sense of
"fading fast" or even "already deceased" but rather in the Jamesonian
sense cited above. It is "recent" and addresses current socioeconomic and
critical contexts. In other words, Zizek's Marxism is only as late as what
it proposes to criticize--the late capitalism so named in the somewhat
hopeful title of Ernest Mandel's 1978 book. Whatever label is attached to
it, Zizek's work fulfills one of the primary goals of Marxist theory, that
is, to harness the "material force of ideas" in an effort to expose and
criticize the workings of capitalism.
Department of English
Gonzaga University
donahue@gonzaga.edu
COPYRIGHT (c) 2002 BRIAN DONAHUE. READERS MAY USE
PORTIONS OF THIS WORK IN ACCORDANCE WITH THE FAIR USE PROVISIONS OF U.S.
COPYRIGHT LAW. IN ADDITION, SUBSCRIBERS AND MEMBERS OF SUBSCRIBED
INSTITUTIONS MAY
USE THE ENTIRE WORK FOR ANY INTERNAL NONCOMMERCIAL PURPOSE BUT, OTHER THAN
ONE COPY SENT BY EMAIL, PRINT OR FAX TO ONE PERSON AT ANOTHER LOCATION FOR
THAT INDIVIDUAL'S PERSONAL USE, DISTRIBUTION OF THIS ARTICLE OUTSIDE OF A
SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION FROM EITHER THE
AUTHOR OR THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS IS EXPRESSLY FORBIDDEN.
THIS ARTICLE AND OTHER CONTENTS OF THIS ISSUE ARE
AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE UNTIL RELEASE OF THE NEXT ISSUE. A
TEXT-ONLY ARCHIVE OF THE JOURNAL IS ALSO AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE.
FOR FULL HYPERTEXT ACCESS TO BACK ISSUES, SEARCH UTILITIES, AND OTHER
VALUABLE FEATURES, YOU OR YOUR INSTITUTION MAY SUBSCRIBE TO
PROJECT MUSE, THE
ON-LINE JOURNALS PROJECT OF THE
JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS.
Notes
1. Hebdige uses this abbreviated
term to accommodate the various "post" terms and discourses that have
emerged in theoretical writing since the late 1960s, especially
postmodernism/postmodernity. See Hiding in the Light, Chapter
8, "Staking out the Posts."
2. See especially Jameson's essay
"Reification and Utopia in Mass Culture," Social Text 1
(1979), reprinted as Chapter 1 of Signatures of the Visible.
3. Jean Baudrillard's writing in the
late 1960s and 1970s offers a critique of the production-oriented labor
theory of value in favor of a consumption-oriented model of sign value;
see Selected Writings, especially Chapters 1-4. The implicit
and explicit critique of dialectical method and teleology can be seen in
many versions of postmodern theory; Lyotard's Postmodern
Condition is exemplary, especially the discussions of postmodern
science and paralogy in Chapters 13 and 14. The generally critical stance
of "French poststructuralists" toward Marxism may be explained partly as a
reaction against the influential role of Communist parties in European
intellectual debates of the 1950s and 1960s, as Burnham suggests:
Lyotard's critique, based as it is on a certain causal relationship
between grand narratives and local actions, is more suited to a culture of
powerful communist parties and unexamined Stalinism than the less rigorous
Marxism to be found in the Anglo-American tradition.... An important flaw
in Lyotard's analysis is that he overestimates the aforementioned
causality. (13)
4. See Lyotard, The Postmodern
Condition; Baudrillard's recent apocalyptic and impressionistic
essays can be found in America, Cool Memories,
and The Transparency of Evil; Deleuze and Guattari develop
their project of "schizoanalysis" in Anti-Oedipus, especially
Section 4; Jameson presents his extended critique of postmodern culture in
Postmodernism.
5. Commenting on the ongoing
globalization of capital and the accompanying triumphalist discourse of
neoliberal market economists, Jameson writes:
Now that, following master thinkers like Hayek, it has become customary to
identify political freedom with market freedom, the motivations behind
ideology no longer seem to need an elaborate machinery of decoding and
hermeneutic reinterpretation; and the guiding thread of all contemporary
politics seems much easier to grasp, namely, that the rich want their
taxes lowered. This means that an older vulgar Marxism may once again be
more relevant to our situation than the newer models. ("Culture" 247)
6. The notion of a historical
transformation of the "real world" into semiotic spectacle is the thesis
of Guy Debord's critique of media-consumer capitalism in Society of
the Spectacle: "everything that was directly lived has moved away
into a representation" (par. 1). Debord, however, has no patience for the
structuralist effort to interpret all phenomena in terms of differential
sign-systems, a project that he sees as the philosophical corollary to
spectacular society: "Structuralism is the thought guaranteed by the
State which regards the present conditions of spectacular
'communication' as an absolute" (par. 202). My citation of Derrida in this
context should by no means be taken as an effort to characterize his work
as part of this "thought guaranteed by the State," merely uncritically
reflecting prevailing semio-capitalist society. On the contrary, the
opening pages of the first chapter of Of Grammatology indicate an
acute critical awareness of the historical determination of the meditation
on writing undertaken in that text: beyond his general emphasis on the
historical dimension of the problem, Derrida mentions specifically the
"death of the civilization of the book" and the rise of cybernetic theory
and the DNA-coding paradigm in biology, among other historically recent
developments, as catalysts for a theory of generalized writing (6-10).
7. See Habermas's Theory of
Communicative Action and Rorty's Contingency, Irony, and
Solidarity, among other texts by these authors.
8. See Butler, Chapter 7, "Arguing with
the Real," in Bodies That Matter.
9. See Zizek's essays "Multiculturalism,
or, the Cultural Logic of Multinational Capitalism" and "A Leftist Plea
for 'Eurocentrism,'" as well as the interview "Japan through a Slovenian
Looking Glass."
10. For an analysis--via Bataille and
Baudrillard--of the Columbine High School shooting incident in Colorado in
terms of a heterological politics of the unassimilable, see Wernick.
11. For discussion of this term, see
Jameson's essay "Cognitive Mapping" as well as the last segment of Chapter
1 of Postmodernism (45-54).
12. My reading of a "darker" truth
behind the film's overt suggestion of nostalgia for lost childhood as an
explanation for Kane's downfall is based on Marshall Deutelbaum's article
"'Rosebud' and the Illusion of Childhood Innocence in Citizen
Kane." Zizek includes Citizen Kane among those films
in which, he claims, Welles depicts a "larger-than-life" individual with
an "ambiguous relationship to morals" but a nonetheless heroic ethical
nature (Metastases 66). My reading suggests a rejection of
this notion that Kane's "acts irradiate a deeper 'ethics of Life itself'"
(66).
13. A useful contrast to this case of
oppressive desire of the mother is raised in the following passage in
which Zizek discusses Lacan's determination of Name-of-the-Father as the
"metaphoric substitute of the desire of the mother" (For They
135). Zizek explains this relationship in terms of the scene from
Hitchcock's North by Northwest in which Roger
Thornhill--certainly also a "pathological narcissist," but one whose story
ends "happily"--is "'mistakenly identified' as the mysterious 'George
Kaplan' and thus hooked on his Name-of-the-Father, his Master-Signifier."
The precise instant of the mistaken identification, Zizek writes,
is the very moment when he raises his hand in order to comply with his
mother's desire by phoning her.... North by Northwest thus
presents a case of "successful" substitution of the paternal metaphor for
the mother's desire. (For They 135)
14. See Susan Jeffords's analysis of
Hollywood masculine-fantasy narratives and the New Right in Hard
Bodies.
Works Cited
Althusser, Louis. "Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses."
Lenin and Philosophy. Trans. Ben Brewster. New York: Monthly
Review, 1971. 127-86.
Baudrillard, Jean. America. Trans. Chris Turner.
London: Verso, 1989.
---. Cool Memories, 1980-1985. Trans. Chris Turner.
London: Verso, 1990.
---. Selected Writings. Ed. Mark Poster. Stanford, CA:
Stanford UP, 1988.
---. The Transparency of Evil: Essays on Extreme
Phenomena. 1990. Trans. James Benedict. London: Verso, 1993.
Burnham, Clint. The Jamesonian Unconscious: The Aesthetics
of Marxist Theory. Durham, NC: Duke UP, 1995.
Butler, Judith. Bodies That Matter: On the Discursive Limits
of "Sex." New York: Routledge, 1993.
Citizen Kane. Dir. Orson Welles. Perf. Orson Welles,
Joseph Cotton, Dorothy Comingore. RKO, 1941.
Debord, Guy. Society of the Spectacle. 1967. Detroit:
Black and Red, 1983.
Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. Anti-Oedipus:
Capitalism and Schizophrenia. 1977. Trans. Robert Hurley, Mark
Seem, and Helen R. Lane. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1983.
Derrida, Jacques. Of Grammatology. Trans. Gayatri
Chakravorty Spivak. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins UP, 1974.
Deutelbaum, Marshall. "'Rosebud' and the Illusion of Childhood
Innocence in Citizen Kane." The Kingdom of Dreams:
Selected Papers from the Tenth Florida State University Conference on
Literature and Film. Ed. Douglas Fowler. Tallahassee: Florida State
UP, 1986. 46-61.
Ebert, Teresa L. "Beyond 'Enlightened False Consciousness' and for
a Red Theory." Div. on Sociological Approaches to Literature, MLA
Convention. Chicago, IL. 28 Dec. 1999.
Gigante, Denise. "Toward a Notion of Critical Self-Creation:
Slavoj Zizek and the 'Vortex of Madness.'" New Literary
History 29 (1998): 153-68.
Habermas, Jürgen. The Theory of Communicative
Action. Trans. Thomas McCarthy. Boston: Beacon, 1984.
Hebdige, Dick. Hiding in the Light: On Images and
Things. New York: Routledge, 1988.
Homer, Sean. "Psychoanalysis, Representation, Politics: On the
(Im)possibility of a Psychoanalytic Theory of Ideology?" University of
Sheffield, Centre for Psychotherapeutic Studies (1995): 16 pars.
<http://www.shef.ac.uk/uni/academic/N-Q/psysc/staff/sihomer/prp.html>.
Jameson, Fredric. "Cognitive Mapping." Cultural Studies. Ed.
Lawrence Grossberg, Cary Nelson, and Paula A. Treichler. New York:
Routledge, 1992. 347-57.
---. "Culture and Finance Capital." Critical Inquiry
24 (1997): 246-65.
---. Late Marxism: Adorno, or, The Persistence of the
Dialectic. London: Verso, 1990.
---. Postmodernism, or, The Cultural Logic of Late
Capitalism. Durham: Duke UP, 1991.
---. Signatures of the Visible. New York: Routledge,
1992.
Jeffords, Susan. Hard Bodies: Hollywood Masculinity in the
Reagan Era. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers UP, 1994.
Lacan, Jacques. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan, Book III:
The Psychoses. Trans. Russell Grigg. Ed. Jacques-Alain Miller.
New York: Norton, 1993.
Lyotard, Jean-François. The Postmodern Condition: A
Report on Knowledge.
Trans. Geoff Bennington and Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P.
1984.
Mandel, Ernest. Late Capitalism. Trans. Joris DeBres.
London: Verso, 1978.
Pulp Fiction. Dir. Quentin Tarantino. Perf. John
Travolta, Samuel L. Jackson, Uma Thurman. Miramax, 1994.
Rorty, Richard. Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity.
New York: Cambridge UP, 1989.
Sloterdijk, Peter. Critique of Cynical Reason. Trans.
Michael Eldred. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1987.
Wernick, Andrew. "Bataille's Columbine: The Sacred Space of Hate."
Ctheory (3 Nov. 1999): 43 pars. <http://www.ctheory.net/text_file.asp?pick=119>.
Williams, Raymond. Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and
Society. 1983. New York: Oxford UP, 1985.
Zizek, Slavoj. For They Know Not What They Do: Enjoyment as
a Political Factor. London: Verso, 1991.
---. "Japan through a Slovenian Looking Glass: Reflections of
Media and Politics and Cinema." Interview. InterCommunication
14 (1995): 40 pars. <http://www.ntticc.or.jp/pub/ic_mag/ic014/zizek/zizek_e.html>.
---. "A Leftist Plea for 'Eurocentrism.'" Critical
Inquiry 24 (1998): 988-1009.
---. Looking Awry: An Introduction to Jacques Lacan through
Popular Culture. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991.
---. The Metastases of Enjoyment: Six Essays on Woman and
Causality. London: Verso, 1994.
---. "Multiculturalism, Or, the Cultural Logic of Multinational
Capitalism." New Left Review 225 (1997): 28-51.
---. The Sublime Object of Ideology. London: Verso,
1989.
---. "The Supposed Subjects of Ideology." Critical
Quarterly 39.2 (1997): 39-59.
|