As soon as, through the movement of those forces tending toward a break,
revolution appears as something possible, with a possibility
that is not abstract, but historically and concretely determined, then in
those moments revolution has taken place.
--Maurice Blanchot
We are left with a simple command, and an infinite responsibility. Be
just with Justice.
--Drucilla Cornell
- This essay attempts to confront perhaps the most obvious and yet
the most difficult challenge of radical social critique: the question of
the practical. Both of its authors have been interested for
many years in various modes of deconstruction and post-Marxism, and we have
attempted, in our separate ways, to expose the limits not only of the
historical discourses of economy and anthropology, but even of some of
the cherished concepts of contemporary left-wing thought. But our work
on multiculturalism, political economy, and cultural studies has brought
us to the limit of our own critiques. At this limit, how does one say
"yes" to the affirmative? How can we, in the words of the famous Marxist
injunction, "prove the truth, that is, the reality and power, the
this-sidedness" of our thinking in practice (Marx and Engels 144)?
- We thus respond here to two challenges. The first
concerns the general perception in many circles that poststructuralist
thought is either a form of quietism with no political consequences or a
reactionary practice that easily slides into the anti-Semitisms and
fascisms of Nazi-era Heidegger and deMan. Much recent work in the
tradition of poststructuralist Marxism, including our own, has been
attacked on one or the other of these grounds. To some, the work seems
merely theoretical and thus utterly impractical. To others, even more
seriously, the work seems counterproductive in its relentless
critique of seemingly promising possibilities for political thought and
action. In other words, poststructuralist and post-Marxist modes of
theory are perceived as merely alternating between a scholastic
cataloguing of utopian (im)possibilities, and a categorical rejection of
all down-to-earth, practical-progressive thought. A great deal has been
written in recent years attempting to disprove these views. One might
mention, among others, Michael Ryan's Marxism and Deconstruction: A
Critical Articulation (1982), Drucilla Cornell's Beyond
Accommodations (1991; new edition 1999), Geoff Bennington's
Legislations (1996), Richard Beardsworth's Derrida and
the Political (1996), Chantel Mouffe's The Democratic
Paradox (2000), and Derrida's own many recent writings on politics,
including, most famously, Specters of Marx (1994), and his
response to the critics of that book in Ghostly Demarcations
(Sprinker ed. 1999). It must be admitted, however, that little of this
work undertakes a deconstructive approach to particular instances of
politico-economic decision-making (although Derrida's writing on South
Africa is one of several interesting exceptions).[1] Our project here would be unimaginable without the
rigorous work of these and many other contemporary theorists. But
whatever its myriad achievements, none of this work has stilled the
well-meaning voices that constantly interpose to it the belittling claims
of brute practicality. All of us have frequently heard these voices: it
is well and good, they say, to debate such things in a seminar room or an
academic journal, but how will any of this help the refugees in Kosovo or
Afghanistan, or feed the homeless, or fight racism, or relieve any of the
other small or large acts of violence and injustice among which we daily
live and work? In this essay, we do not shrink from such questions.
Instead, we embrace them and, in a preliminary way, attempt to take up what
we acknowledge to be this necessary burden.
- The second matter to which we attempt to respond
is the one that Roberto Mangabeira Unger has elaborated: the question of
remaining committed to an ultimate radicality of thought even as one
examines and endorses certain sorts of practical reformism, such as
affirmative action and welfare. As Unger observes, "The idea of
institutional tinkering, or part-by-part change, has often been
associated with the abandonment of the challenge to the fundamental
institutions of society," and "Conversely, the conception of such a
challenge has just as often been connected with the idea that our
institutional structures exist as indivisible systems, standing or
falling together" (Unger 19). Marx himself sometimes positioned himself
in such a way as to rule out the possibility of anything but an absolute
transformation of society. In the "Critique of the Gotha Program," for
example, Marx deploys a logic that seems to suggest that any given
social arrangement can be declared either bourgeois or revolutionary,
with nothing in between, and with an absolute divide between the two.
Marx will occasionally grade the various forms of bourgeois society, as
when he argues that "vulgar democracy... towers mountains" over the Gotha
Program's projected Lassallian arrangements (Marx and Engels 538-39), but
he also insists that all bourgeois arrangements remain bourgeois through
and through and hence should be rigorously rejected. And by such logic,
Marx finds himself declaring at the end of this text, for example, that
"a general prohibition of child labor" is "incompatible with the
existence of large-scale industry" and therefore not only an "empty,
pious wish," but even "reactionary" (Marx and Engels 541). We cite such
a passage not to suggest it somehow vitiates the whole Marxist project,
within whose broad lines we continue to place our own, but rather to
underline our contrasting belief that certain modes of practical
political reform are entirely commensurate with more radical forms of
theoretical critique. Here, we consider whether certain versions of
affirmative action and welfare might remain faithful to what Jean-Luc
Nancy, Maurice Blanchot, and Giorgio Agamben, among others, have
described as a community beyond the limits of all prevailing models of
community, a community that is not the end-result of some
forever-deferred cataclysm but that is, rather, uncovered or recognized
in the acknowledgment of our being-in-common.[2] In this way, we position ourselves at one remove
from Unger's twin concerns regarding "the dangerous limiting case of
transformative politics": on the one hand, the demand for nothing less
than an absolute revolution, an all-transformative intervention within an
imagined History; on the other hand, the inevitable lapse into a
"pessimism" about change that no longer aspires to do more than
"humanize the inevitable" (Unger 19, 20). The first case is that of the
"would be revolutionar[y]" suffering from a "hypertrophy of the will,"
while the second is that of the "disillusioned ex-Marxist become the
institutionally conservative social democrat" (Unger 20). Here, we seek
to avoid either of these extremes and agree generally with Unger that it
is valid and important to experiment at the border of existing social
arrangements--that is, to imagine practical, incremental reforms even as
one also tries to think a society that, by contrast, wholly exceeds the
exclusionary practices of the present moment.
- In what follows, we first critique at length the
reasoning of some of the well-known legal decisions of recent years that
address the issues of affirmative action and welfare, in order to suggest
how and why the prevailing thought on either issue has reached an
impasse. Then we go on to discover the possibility of a new opening of
theory and practice that takes place at the very limit of the prevailing
logic on either issue.
1. Toward a Theory of Affirmative Action Without White Affirmation
- In the third presidential debate of 2000, candidates George W.
Bush and Albert Gore, Jr. jousted over affirmative action. Gore
attempted to show that Bush did not accept affirmative action's
fundamental principles--by which he apparently meant the celebrated
opinion of Supreme Court Justice Louis Powell in Regents of
California v. Bakke (1978). Bush, conversely, asserted that he
supported the Texas system: that is, the system instituted in the wake of
Hopwood v. Texas (1996), in which ten percent of every public
high school graduate class is guaranteed admission into Texas higher
education. But there was clear agreement over the matter of "quotas."
Both vigorously asserted their opposition to that form of affirmative
action. Indeed, the term "quotas" has become in recent years the
all-purpose bugbear in affirmative action discourse.
- But precisely what are we referring to when we
use this crucial term? The commonplace in this regard is that "quota"
signals an interest in placing racial minorities in jobs and admitting
them as students irrespective of merit. Thus, according to this account,
quota-based affirmative action involves the placement of unqualified or
considerably less qualified racial minorities into sought-after
positions. But as anyone knows who has served, for example, on an
admitting committee for graduate students at a major university, the
question of qualifications simply cannot be settled: excellent students
come from all types of colleges, with all forms of credentials, and with
all manner of test scores and grades; and the same is true of mediocre
students. Success in graduate school is premised on factors that are
impossible to weigh according to any simple standards. The enormous
body of literature surrounding, for example, the matter of standardized
test scores should have convinced anyone long ago of the foolishness of
predicting talent and performance.[3]
- Something else, of course, is at stake in the rhetoric of
"quotas," and while it might be obvious to some, it is also worth
rehearsing. One can start with the key decision in Hopwood v.
Texas (1996; also known as "Hopwood II"), where a striking series
of consecutive paragraphs signals some hard kernel of ideology in their
very repetitiveness. The decision, handed down 18 March 1996 by the
United States Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit, rejects the idea
that a state or a state institution has "a compelling state interest in
remedying the present effects of past societal discrimination" and makes
clear the limits of remedial action (Hopwood 949). The
three-member court unanimously and approvingly cites Justice Powell's
decision in Wygant v. Jackson Board of Education (1986):
In the absence of particularized findings, a court could uphold remedies
that are ageless in their reach into the past, and timeless in their
ability to affect the future. (Hopwood 950)
And again, the Court cites Powell in Wygant:
A remedy reaching all education within a state addresses a putative
injury that is vague and amorphous. It has "no logical stopping point."
(950)
Then, citing the Supreme Court's plurality opinion in City of
Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co. (1989):
The "evidence" relied upon by the dissent, history of school
desegregation in Richmond and numerous congressional reports, does little
to define the scope of any injury to minority contractors in Richmond or
the necessary remedy. The factors relied upon by the dissent could
justify a preference of any size or duration. (950-1)
And, finally, the Fifth Circuit declares in its own voice that the
previous decision of the district court, the decision they are
overturning, must be rejected because it "employs no viable limiting
principle" (950), and because the
very program at issue here shows how remedying such past wrongs may be
expanded beyond any reasonable limits. (951)
"Ageless and timeless," "no logical stopping point,"
"preference of any size or duration," "no viable limiting principle,"
"beyond any reasonable limits": what each of these moments has in common
is an assertion that affirmative action can go too far, can overrun what
Wygant calls the "limiting [of] the remedial purpose to the
'governmental unit involved'" (qtd. in Hopwood 952, n. 44).
The argument here is clear: the Court in Hopwood II asserts that the
University of Texas Law School is only permitted to take account of its
own local and particular discriminatory practices (not those of society in
general, or Texas education, or even the University of Texas) and only
with regard to citizens of the State of Texas.
- And indeed, nested in this flurry of limits, the
Court asserts yet one more--here once again citing Croson:
Relief for such an ill-defined wrong could extend until the percentage
of public contracts awarded to [minority businesses] in Richmond mirrored
the percentage of minorities in the population as a whole. (950; for
original, see Croson 498)
In the context of all of the other, repetitive phrases regarding "no
reasonable limits," the logic of the whole becomes visible: parity or
equivalence between the state's racial categorization and public contract
awards, or between racial categorization and law school admissions,
would be the moment when one has gone "beyond" the "viable," when one has
clearly exceeded all "reasonable limits." In other words, "reasonable"
affirmative action must never approach an equalization of opportunities
between and among racial categories. What will remain absolutely
unthinkable, unreasonable, and without any "viable" stopping point or
limit would be a world in which an X percent statewide African-American
population would yield an X percent African-American entering class at the
University of Texas Law School.
- This is, then, one of the crucial decipherings
for the term "quota": a system in which affirmative action targets might
produce equal opportunities. It is as simple as that. (Conversations
about "merit," therefore, are merely code for continued white supremacy;
as Richard Delgado, through the fictional professor "Rodrigo," writes:
"The first problem I have with the idea of merit has to do with its
majoritarian quality.... Merit is what the victors impose" [Delgado
71].) And while it is certainly true that Hopwood in
general represents the rhetorical opposite or end of affirmative action
(striking down remedies for any but the most egregious, intentional, and
local examples of discrimination and exclusion), one should not too
quickly presume that one will find a different logic operating
elsewhere--in Justice Powell's decision in Bakke, for
example, which Hopwood explicitly seeks to overturn. Powell
quite clearly asserts the same logic of "boundlessness'" in his decision:
In the school cases, the States were required by court order to redress
the wrongs worked by specific instances of racial discrimination. That
goal was far more focused than the remedying of the effects of "societal
discrimination," an amorphous concept of injury that may be ageless in
its reach into the past. (Regents 307)
What precisely does Powell imply here by "amorphous" and "ageless"?
Earlier in the opinion, he writes:
The clock of our liberties cannot be turned back to 1868.... It is far
too late to argue that the guarantee of equal protection to all persons
permits the recognition of special wards entitled to a degree of greater
protection than that accorded others. "The Fourteenth Amendment is not
directed solely against discrimination due to a "two-class theory"--that
is, based upon differences between "white" and Negro." Hernandez, 347
U.S., at 478. (Regents 295)
Powell in essence argues that the Fourteenth Amendment embodies a
"two-class theory" that, if it were 1868, might be of relevance for
deciding the matter. One hundred and ten years later, however, he
asserts that the Fourteenth Amendment has other agendas; somewhere
between 1868 and 1978, then, the Fourteenth Amendment was transformed.
There was a time limit, he asserts, on strict construction of the
Amendment.[4] During this period, the
mode of interpretation of the Amendment shifted from strict to loose
construction, from original intent to new historical needs and
exigencies. Powell dates this transition by signaling that something new
has taken place "over the last 30 years"--meaning, roughly, 1950
(Regents 293). The implication is that by 1950 it was "too
late" for race-based remedies. The fact that Powell here directly
alludes in his language to the most famous passage in Brown v.
Board of Education (1954) tells us a great deal.
Brown had argued that, "we cannot turn the clock back to
1896 when Plessy v. Ferguson was written. We must consider
public education in the light of its full development and its present
place in American life throughout the Nation" (Brown
492-3). Thus, Brown suggests that Plessy (the
notorious "separate yet equal" case) belongs to a historical moment, and
Powell does much the same, but to reverse effect: the project of
Brown, he concludes, has made race-based affirmative action
an impossibility. Affirmative action at the University of California is
thus more like Plessy than Brown, according to
Powell.
- The effects of an "ageless" remedy for social
discrimination are multiple, according to Powell. "Gender-based
distinctions," for example, "might become part of affirmative action,"
although, as Powell writes, "gender-based classifications do not share"
the "lengthy and tragic history" of race-based classifications
(Regents 303). More troubling, he indicates, is that while
gender involves only "two possible classifications," the matter of
"racial and ethnic preferences presents far more complex and intractable
problems than gender-based classifications" (303):
The white "majority" itself is composed of various minority groups, most
of which can lay claim to a history of prior discrimination at the hands
of the State and private individuals. Not all of these groups can
receive preferential treatment and corresponding judicial tolerance of
distinctions drawn in terms of race and nationality, for then the only
"majority" left would be a new minority of white Anglo-Saxon Protestants.
(Regents 295-6)
Thus, the hinge for Powell's determination of that which is too unbounded
for consideration in matters of affirmative action is precisely that
moment when whiteness would no longer constitute a majority. In other
words, affirmative action, for Powell, is a "majority" solution to the
problem of minorities that can operate only to the limit of the
maintenance of majority status for whites. In this way, the limit of
affirmative action in Powell's opinion in Bakke is precisely
the same as the limit described in Hopwood, and the one thing
that the entire tradition of court decisions regarding affirmative action
can never tolerate, therefore, is the disenabling of white privilege and
thus the disenabling of "race."[5]
Although Ronald Dworkin suggests that the "ultimate goal [of
University-based affirmative action] is to lessen not to increase the
importance of race in American social and professional life" (Dworkin
294), this most certainly has not turned out to be the case in
practice--not since Bakke, at least. In this regard, all
liberal scholarly celebrations of the Powell opinion's "pragmatic
accommodation" and "shining virtues" (Post 24, 20) and its "salutary"
character of opening up rather than closing debate on affirmative action
(Sunstein 118) are misguided. If the Powell opinion settled anything, it
was that affirmative action must be accommodated to the presumed views of
the "white majority."
- Indeed, there are so many moments of dicta in
this regard in Powell's opinion, separate and distinct from any form of
legal argumentation, that it is difficult to read it without being struck
by the sheer force of its defense of white privilege. In a moment
(lurking in Powell's footnotes) that interests the distinguished legal
scholar Reva Seigel, Powell marshals onto the side of his argument the
"outrage" of white people:
All state-imposed classifications that rearrange burdens and benefits on
the basis of race are likely to be viewed with deep resentment by the
individuals burdened. The denial to innocent persons of equal rights and
opportunities may outrage those so deprived and therefore may be
perceived to be invidious. These individuals are likely to find little
comfort in the notion that the deprivation they are asked to endure is
merely the price of membership in the dominant majority and that its
imposition is inspired by the supposedly benign purpose of aiding
others. One should not lightly dismiss the inherent unfairness of, and
the perception of mistreatment that accompanies, a system of allocating
benefits and privileges on the basis of skin color and ethnic origin.
(Regents 294, n. 34)
One might want to underline the words "merely the price of
membership in the dominant majority" in order to underscore the way that
Powell takes as a given the continued existence of a "dominant" white
majority, and that even an affirmative action that in no way imperils
this status might cross the line of "inherent unfairness." In this
sense, affirmative action theory as embedded in the Powell opinion and
its many later judicial and scholarly commentaries begins from the
assumption that affirmative action may only set as its goal a minimal
sort of tokenism. Again, one perhaps wants to underline the extra-legal
character of this moment: a U.S. Supreme Court justice decides here to
speak for the white race rather than on behalf of a legal principle.
- And there is still to consider in this regard one more
matter buried in the Powell decision that will permit the theorization of
affirmative action in a far more explicit way. It should be remembered, of
course, that Powell's opinion in Bakke pleased no one on the
court: that Justices Burger, Stewart, Rehnquist, and Stevens affirmed the
overturning of the University of California affirmative action program
but wrote a combined dissent to Powell; and that Justices White, Brennan,
Marshall, and Blackmun accepted Powell's logic only at its most minimal
point, Section V-C, which is one paragraph long and provides no guidance
as to how "the competitive consideration of race" might continue
(Regents 320). Historically, however, the totality of
Powell's decision has become increasingly important, with large chucks of
its entirely solo logic cited in later court decisions.
- Justice Powell relied not only on his reading of
the Fourteenth Amendment and of Brown v. Board of Education in
order to reject California-Davis's version of affirmative action. He
also linked his opinion on several occasions to a network of Supreme Court
and other court cases concerning Asian-Americans. Section III-A, for
example, which was joined by Justice White and thus perhaps stands
firmer than any other part of the decision except for V-C, ends by citing
approvingly the language from Hirabayashi v. United States
(1942) and Korematsu v. United States (1944):
Racial and ethnic classifications, however, are subject to stringent
examination without regard to these additional characteristics {i.e.,
"discreteness" and "insularity" of the classification}. We declared as
much in the first cases explicitly to recognize racial distinctions as
suspect:
"Distinctions between citizens solely because of their ancestry are by
their very nature odious to a free people whose institutions are founded
upon the doctrine of equality." Hirabayashi, 320 U.S., at 100.
"[A]ll legal restrictions which curtail the civil rights of a single
racial group are immediately suspect. This is not to say that all such
restrictions are unconstitutional. It is to say that courts must subject
them to the most rigid scrutiny." Korematsu, 323 U.S., at 216.
The Court has never questioned the validity of these pronouncements.
Racial and ethnic distinctions of any sort are inherently suspect and
thus call for the most exacting judicial examination.
(Regents 290-91)
These perhaps fine-sounding words appear in cases that leave the
blackest mark on the Supreme Court's record in the twentieth century.
Hirabayashi and Korematsu are the
Japanese-American Exclusion Order cases; both affirm the Constitutional
authority to discriminate and exclude U.S. citizens on the basis of race
if "a group of one national extraction may menace that safety more than
others" (Hirabayashi 101) and if it is "deemed necessary
because of the presence of an unascertained number of disloyal members of
the group" (Korematsu 218).
- Both cases were reopened through Congressional inquiry
shortly after Powell's decision in Bakke, and the final
Congressional Report concluded that the cases had been "overruled in the
court of history."[6] Yet, of course, the
cases stood as precedent in 1978, just as they stand today. As Reggie Oh
and Frank Wu have written, "Korematsu remains controlling case law" (167).
The cases constitutionally authorize a two-tier or two-class model of U.S.
citizenship, upholding the Exclusion Orders during a time of emergency
even as they affirm Asian-American "status as citizens"
(Hirabayashi 113-14).
- Thus, the question of what Powell has
accomplished by yoking his decision in Bakke to these cases
is a curious one, and yet one which must be asked because Powell
continues along the same lines in Section III-B of the decision. Here,
he includes a long footnote that uses the Exclusion Order cases to
declare that "no Western state... can claim that it has always treated
Japanese and Chinese in a fair and evenhanded manner" in order to
demonstrate that an affirmation of general "minority" entitlement will
open the door to an unbounded number of groups which might claim
discrimination (Regents 297, n. 37l; also 292, 294).
- Powell is here operating by complex analogy. When he
writes, "This is not to say that all such restrictions are
unconstitutional. It is to say that courts must subject them to the most
rigid scrutiny," he suggests that the logic of the state of emergency in
Hirabayashi and Korematsu will be applied to
California-Davis in order to ascertain whether the State of California's
racial hierarchies justify the emergency measure of quota-based
affirmative action. For Powell, of course, California does not meet the
test. Thus, the same standard which permits the Japanese
concentration camps denies the need for affirmative action. But
this is more than the mere application of some clear and determinate
standard in two separate cases. By thinking these two instances together
as a coherent political strategy, one can conclude that the logic of the
limit in Bakke is double: Affirmative action can only
proceed so long as it does not disturb white privilege, while at the
same time the Constitutional protection of raceless citizenship extends
also only to the point where white privilege senses its disturbance.
The Supreme Court, then, has clarified the matter of racial politics in
the following way: the only race that always counts (or matters) is the
white race. All other races are counted (that is, enumerated and taken
account of) flexibly, and this depends entirely on whether such counting
is seen as a furtherance or hindrance to white majoritarian rule.
- Hirabayashi and
Korematsu are by any measure highly exceptional cases, but
such exceptions, as Carl Schmitt argues, reveal the precise location of
"sovereignty": "Sovereign is he who decides on the exception" (Schmitt
5). "What characterizes an exception is principally unlimited authority,
which means the suspension of the entire existing order," and therefore
"the exception reveals most clearly the essence of the state's authority"
(Schmitt 12, 13). Exceptions to Constitutional norms, then, are not
precisely exceptional:
The rule proves nothing; the exception proves everything: It confirms not
only the rule but also its existence, which derives only from the
exception. (Schmitt 15)
It is only in the exception that one can see clearly the grounding of the
norm. In this case, legal racelessness, legal color-blindness, is
premised, grounded, and founded upon a bedrock of Constitutional white
privilege, of white supremacy. The law of white supremacy "is not wholly
beyond the limits of the Constitution and is not to be condemned merely
because in other and in most circumstances racial distinctions are
irrelevant" (Hirabayashi 101). Powell's founding of all
future affirmative action theory on the base of Hirabayashi
and Korematsu thus assures theoretically that affirmative
action must content itself with results far below those that would permit
the equalization of racial opportunities in the United States. The body
of affirmative action decisions in the U.S. since 1978 are coextensive
with the entire history of state-based and state-sponsored racial
hierarchies and exclusions. (From a related perspective, as Oh and Wu
suggest, the affirmative action decision Adarand Constructors v.
Pena (1995) explicitly reinforces the logic of
Korematsu and lays the groundwork for a future related
race-emergency decision [182]).
- One sees the results of Powell throughout the
country, in institutions that claim to be strongly operating under the
principles of affirmative action. At Michigan State University, for
example, where Michaelsen teaches, the official affirmative action goals
of colleges and departments are set far below general population
distributions and are instead keyed to a concept of market
"availability" of potential faculty. In addition, in setting unit goals
all "minorities" are lumped together; thus, at a time when the national
minority population officially nears 30% and rapidly heads toward 50%,
the total target for the Department of English is 10.6% minority
composition (or six out of approximately fifty faculty). The
implications are serious, as the University's Affirmative Action Officer
reports: once these minimal targets are met, no University-level support
need be offered in terms of the hiring of additional minority faculty
members. "The test is whether there is underutilization," according to
the UAAO. Since the English Department has two American Indian faculty
members, one Asian/Pacific Islander, and two Black faculty members, no
"unit hiring goal" is set in terms of Hispanic faculty, for example, even
though the Department has no Chicano/Latino faculty members. There are, in
essence, too many other minorities already in place, and there
currently is 1.6% "over-utilization" of minority faculty positions in the
Department from the University's perspective. Indeed, the Department
has been officially notified that it has no "hiring goal" at all at the
present time as far as racial minorities are concerned. In this game, no
unit can easily or even reasonably manage to achieve parity with larger
social demographics, and "minorities" are condemned to super-minority or
"minority-minority" status.[7]
- None of this is surprising in the wake of
Bakke, and MSU in this regard is neither better nor worse
than its peer institutions. Everything in the case law concerning
affirmative action would steer an institution in this direction. For
example, in Fullilove v. Klutznick (1980), a case that
considered the Public Works Employment Act of 1977, the Supreme Court
found that a 10% set-aside for federally funded contracts was
constitutional, while in the Croson decision, which was
cited at
the crucial ideological moment in Hopwood, the court threw
out a 30% set-aside instituted by a major U.S. city (a city, by the way,
that claimed at the time a 50% minority population). The Supreme Court
produced a highly contorted logic in Croson in order to
reach the conclusion that one form of set-aside was constitutional and
the other not. Justice O'Connor, writing the majority opinion, argued,
for example, that the U.S. Congress had stronger powers in regard to
determining set-asides and noted that the Thirteenth and Fourteenth
Amendments themselves had limited the powers of states to undertake their
own initiatives and enlarged those of the U.S. Congress (City of
Richmond 490). Thus, in part, Richmond's plan was overturned
because it represented local rather than federal affirmative action.
- But it would be difficult not to see in these
two opinions that the Supreme Court has determined that affirmative
action has an appropriate target goal, and that it is closer to 10%
inclusion than it is to 30%. Justice O'Connor writes tellingly in
Croson: "the 30% quota cannot be said to be narrowly
tailored to any goal, except perhaps outright racial balancing"
(City of Richmond 507). This is precisely the heart of the
matter: 10% tokenism is acceptable to the Supreme Court, while 30%
"racial balancing" is not (even though "racial balancing," or attention
to affirmative action with regard to population, would go far
further than 30%). Therefore, when one finds that a Research 1
institution such as Michigan State has adopted a roughly 10% plan, it is
clear that the University seeks to position itself in relation to the
case law in a space where its policy cannot easily be contravened. In
fact, it is in Croson that the logic of "availability" is
laid down as law in the clearest fashion. But the results of this
"lowballing" of affirmative action targets are also perfectly clear.
- One related area in which Croson
completely overturned Fullilove, rather than distorted it,
concerns the matter of statistical analysis. Fullilove had
cited approvingly a House Committee on Small Business report that
had argued that statistical disparities constituted prima facie
evidence of discrimination:
While minority persons comprise about 16 percent of the Nation's
population, of the 13 million businesses in the United States, only
382,000, or approximately 3.0 percent, are owned by minority
individuals. The most recent data from the Department of Commerce also
indicates that the gross receipts of all businesses in this country
totals about $2,540.8 billion, and of this amount only $16.6 billion, or
about 0.65 percent was realized by minority business concerns.
These statistics are not the result of random chance. The presumption
most be made that past discriminatory systems have resulted in present
economic inequities. (qtd. in Fullilove 465)
And the Court concludes on this point: "we are satisfied that Congress
had abundant historical basis from which it could conclude that
traditional procurement practices, when applied to minority businesses,
could perpetuate the effects of prior discrimination"
(Fullilove 478).
- Croson's rejection of this sort of
statistical evaluation is sweeping: "But where special qualifications are
necessary, the relevant statistical pool for purposes of demonstrating
discriminatory exclusion must be the number of minorities qualified to
undertake the particular task" (Croson 501-02). "Blacks may
be disproportionately attracted to industries other than construction,"
the Court argues (Croson 503). And the court describes as
"non-racial factors" such matters as "deficiencies in working capital,
inability to meet bonding requirements, unfamiliarity with bidding
procedures, and disability caused by an inadequate track record"
(Croson 498-99). Thus, according to Croson,
affirmative action begins and ends with things as they are in the present
moment. The fact that in the city of Richmond, with a minority population
base of 50%, 0.67% of the city's recent contracts had been awarded to
minority firms belongs to a network of "inherently unmeasurable claims of
past wrongs" (Croson 506). The Supreme Court in the area of
affirmative action has long been and has continued to be the protector,
then, of white privilege, accepting or rejecting various affirmative
action plans and evidence of discrimination entirely on the basis of
whether percentage hiring/contracting goals for such programs are kept to
a bare minimum. Every time the Supreme Court invokes its logic of
"unboundedness," therefore, the dirty secret is that the Court means that
a particular program has come too close to racial redress. At times, the
Court completely strips away its own masking of this agenda, as in
Croson, in which a 10% set-aside is declared "flexible,"
while a 30% set-aside is deemed a "quota." Here, the Court declares its
preference for not calculating discrimination and the limit of
deracialization, while more typically (and even in Croson)
the court rhetorically has rested on the logic of rejection of any
"amorphous claim" for a program "of any size or duration"
(Croson 499, 505).
- The absolute disaster of attempting to build an
affirmative action program atop the logic of Powell and the Supreme Court
decisions that follow is clear, then, but for one exception. As is well
known, Powell often is celebrated (even by his detractors) for Section IV
of the opinion, in which he affirms the "benefits that flow from an
ethnically diverse student body" and the first amendment "freedom of the
university" (Regents 306, 312). As is also well known, this
limited defense of affirmative action has become the crucial matter in
all subsequent affirmative action discussion.
- Indeed, the summary judgment issued in
Gratz v. Bollinger (2000), which ruled that the University
of Michigan's undergraduate affirmative action program (at least in its
most recent incarnation) is constitutional, turns on the question of
diversity, and here one should first note the language that the Court
reiterates from Plaintiffs' arguments:
Plaintiffs have presented no argument or evidence rebutting the
University Defendants' assertion that a racially and ethnically diverse
student body gives rise to educational benefits for both minority and
non-minority students. In fact, during oral argument, counsel for
Plaintiffs indicated his willingness to assume, for purposes of these
motions, that diversity in institutional settings of higher education is
"good, important, and valuable." Counsel for Plaintiffs, however,
contends that "good, important, and valuable" is not enough, and that the
diversity rationale is too amorphous and ill-defined, and "too limitless,
timeless, and scopeless," to rise to the level of a compelling interest.
According to counsel for Plaintiffs, the University's diversity rationale
has "no logical stopping point" but rather is a "permanent regime" in
direct conflict with strict scrutiny standards. (Gratz
25)
It is here that something novel perhaps enters the case law of
affirmative action: an affirmation of that which is unlimited, rather
than minimal, in Judge Duggan's rejection of Plaintiff's argument.
Already one can note some guarded celebration in liberal quarters
regarding the Gratz affirmation of affirmative action, but
Gratz comes with important and barbed qualifiers in its
unwillingness to determine the limit of affirmative action. First, "in
other contexts, i.e. the construction industry context" (which
historically has been another important site for affirmative action law),
a diversity law rationale may well be "too amorphous and ill-defined"
(Gratz 25). Thus, what Powell has left as affirmative
action's only leg to stand on will function only in an educational
context, with its specialized needs in terms of diversity.
- Second, Gratz precisely reflects
Powell's opinion in Bakke (and the limiting logic of the
combined Fullilove and Croson decisions) in its
rejection of quotas. Most dramatically, Gratz signals its
agreement with the Supreme Court in specifying some indistinct numerical
limit to affirmative action:
A university's interest in achieving the educational benefits that flow
from a diverse student body does not justify an admissions program
designed to admit a predetermined number or proportion of minority
students. Instead, a university must carefully design its system to fall
between these two competing ends of the spectrum, i.e., between a system
that completely fails to achieve a meaningful level of diversity, under
which the benefits associated with a diverse student body will never be
realized, and a rigid quota system, which is clearly unconstitutional
under Justice Powell's opinion in Bakke.
(Gratz 31-2)
Thus, "the fact that the University cannot articulate a set number or
percentage of minority students that would constitute the requisite level
of diversity" poses no problem for Judge Duggan, because the "requisite
level" is already limited by Bakke (Gratz 25).
- Gratz, read carefully, thus affirms only
that proper affirmative action falls somewhere between total "failure" to
diversify and quotas (or "racial balancing"). It remains balanced
precariously between, roughly, the 10% and 30% continuum, and likely
closer to the former than the latter, given the earlier case law.
- What Gratz does affirm turns
entirely and merely, then, on "diversity," and Judge Duggan's decision
includes several pages of reference to Patricia Y. Gurin's contribution
to a very large document prepared by the University of Michigan toward
its defense, entitled, "The Compelling Need for Diversity in Higher
Education." Though a number of more famous commentators weigh in with
pages on the history and results of racism and affirmative action (Derek
Bok, Eric Foner, and the like), it is clear that the most interesting
part of the document is Gurin's, and her claim is that she has generated the
first quantified results of the benefits of diversity.
- Duggan writes: "The University Defendants have presented
this Court with solid evidence regarding the educational benefits that
flow from a racially and ethnically diverse student body" and it is quite
likely that Gurin's findings as well as similar sorts of future studies
will now become part of the next phase of defense of university-based
affirmative action programs (Gratz 21). It is thus worth
pondering the implications of Gurin's argument, in order to understand
whether affirmative action theory finally has broken through the barrier
of white privilege or instead has recapitulated it in some new but
entirely recognizable form.
- Gurin's text refers to an enormous body of
literature on psychological development in order to advance a complex
thesis whose main features can be boiled down to the following:
College students are still psychologically unformed in terms of
their positioning in a "pre-reflective stage of judgment" (Gurin,
"Theoretical" 5);
Late adolescent and early adult experiences, when they are
discontinuous enough from the home environment and complex enough to
offer new ideas and possibilities, can be critical sources of
development. ("Theoretical" 2)
College students, therefore, in order to engage in "deep thinking" and in
order generally to "help... democracy thrive" through reflexive acts of
citizenship, must be thrown into a college environment that is
sufficiently racially and culturally different from the one they have
occupied until age eighteen ("Theoretical" 4, 6). The particular
categories of useful outcomes include such matters as "growth in active
thinking processes," "engagement and motivation" concerning learning and
thinking, as well as general "citizenship engagement," "racial/cultural
engagement," and recognition of the "compatibility of differences" in
modern society (Gurin, "Studies" 4).
- Several levels of analysis are necessary to
understand the implications of these arguments, but first one should
acknowledge that Gurin's text is attempting to salvage affirmative action
within the set of highly narrow constraints imposed by the Supreme
Court's previous decisions. Her general goals in this regard
often are admirable, including the "disrupt[ion]" of a "pattern" of
post-college "segregation," and here it is possible to square her goals
with those of an affirmative action of deracialization (Gurin,
"Empirical" 2). Gurin's defense can never go far enough, however, given
the discursive constraints imposed on the defense in Gratz,
and major portions of the structure of the argument prove problematic on
closer examination.
- First, to the extent that a dynamic shift or
change in racial/cultural milieu for college-age students is necessary
for the achievement of important social objectives, such as thinking
itself, the argument is weakened by the fact that the universally
positive social benefits she cites are only possible, in the first place,
within a society that is segregated. In other words, if the U.S. were
not segregated in the first place--if college students had already been
brought up in a diverse environment--then no such outcomes would be
possible. By defining and valuing critical thinking in this way, the
argument could be interpreted as implicitly supporting the maintenance of a
geographically racialized United States.
- Second, to the extent that one of the key
outcomes is greater "knowledge and awareness" of racial/cultural
difference, the argument values "an increasingly heterogeneous and
complex society" ("Studies" 4; "Theoretical" 6). "It is discourse over
conflict, not unanimity, that helps democracy thrive" ("Theoretical" 6).
Rather than defending affirmative action as anti-racialist practice, as
deracialization, therefore, the argument subtly promotes
difference-construction and difference-building, in order to continue to
exploit such differences for intellectual purposes. Here one would need
to confront the text's fibrillation when using the terms "race" and
"culture"--a fibrillation that is perhaps symptomatic, since the two are
notoriously difficult to disentangle analytically. As Michaelsen has
argued elsewhere at length, there is no benign concept of "culture" or
"cultural difference" that might be separated from "race" and "racial
difference." The ideas of cultural difference and cultural pluralism in
this century simply replace "race" in anthropological thought, and the
discourse of "culture" is therefore a product of racial thought. To the
extent that there are lived experiences of cultural difference in the
United States, they remain tied necessarily to the heritage of race
violence and exclusion in such a way as to always function analogously
when made to operate politically.
- Finally, one should note that the diversity argument in
Gurin's text primarily and perhaps fundamentally emphasizes the benefits
that accrue to white student populations ("Empirical" 4). In
contradistinction, "peer interaction must be considered in more complex
ways for African American students. These findings suggest the supportive
function of group identity for African American students, and the
potentially positive effects of having sufficient numbers of same-race
peers" ("Empirical" 5). Gurin believes that difference benefits everyone,
intellectually and democratically, although she also argues that a
substantially African-American college environment for African-American
students may well benefit them in precisely the same ways that a diverse
environment benefits whites. In other words, the world of education need
not be reformed in the manner of the University of Michigan, unless the
needs of whites constitute the primary agenda. For example,
benefit for African-Americans would accrue equally well in a world of
primarily black colleges, with all African-Americans attending them rather
than historically white institutions. In this way, the University of
Michigan's defense of its affirmative action policy is continuous with all
of the affirmative action decisions in arguing from the position of white
needs.
- But the privileging of white benefit in the
argument should come as no surprise to those who know the
Wygant decision, which explicitly reversed any form of
affirmative action on the basis of a "role model" theory.[8] In other words, any argument for affirmative action
that claims that historically racialized students will benefit from
classrooms run by similarly racialized teachers is struck down in
Wygant as a reintroduction of Plessy's
exclusionary logic:
Carried to its logical extreme, the idea that black students are better
off with black teachers could lead to the very system the Court rejected
in Brown v. Board of Education. (Wygant 276)
After Wygant, then, the only avenue left to pursue is
precisely the one that Gurin's text takes up: that whites benefit from
teachers and peers of color. In this way, the University of Michigan's
defense of its affirmative action policy is continuous with all of the
affirmative action decisions in arguing from the position of white needs.
- To be perfectly clear here: this argument does
not reject the very limited inroads that have been made in the wake of
Bakke and that may come if Gratz remains the
law of the land (increasingly unlikely as this may be, given more recent
developments).[9] It is true, however,
that the thinking that underlies this tradition is one that has a
coherent relationship to the logic of Hopwood and thus to
the logic of anti-affirmative action. The coherence takes place around
the determination of the limit of affirmative action as a permanent
system of affirming and supporting hierarchical racial/cultural
difference rather than a project of deracialization. Deracialization's
promise cannot be realized until a moment when the historic "races" that
live and work in the United States find themselves with truly equal
opportunities all the way down, in a pattern of economic well-being and
career prestige that matches population statistics. One clear roadblock
to deracialization is a hundreds-of-years-old pattern of general economic
and social inequality amongst the historic "races." The disruption of
the pattern depends, minimally, not on the achievements of diversity but
upon the ending of deep structural inequalities.
- Affirmative action explicitly has separated
itself from this goal after Bakke, and the entire line
of post-Bakke court decisions operate as one.[10] These decisions, in fact, take their place as
merely part of a whole landscape of history and policy--including the
colonization and reservationization of Native America, African-American
slavery, the Treaty of Guadalupe Hidalgo, Jim Crow, the Chinese Exclusion
Act and its reiterations, the WWII concentration camps for Japanese
Americans, Manning Marable's formulation of capitalism's underdevelopment
of black America, and in general what Charles Mills calls "the racial
contract"--in which minority citizenship in the United States remains
constantly at risk or even impossible to inaugurate. As it was in 1868
so it remains in the twenty-first century, when the "savage inequalities" of
racialization, to borrow Jonathan Kozol's phrase, are as much on evidence
as they were one hundred and thirty five years ago.[11]
- One possible redefinition, then, of affirmative
action that might take us beyond a mere reiteration of the past (and this
is precisely the one that none of the various courts have taken
seriously) is as follows: affirmative action should be the white race's
expenditure
without reserve of its privilege. Phrasing the matter in this way,
affirmative action is about deracialization and the disempowerment of a
whiteness that will remain in place for as long as there are income,
savings, and property-holding discrepancies between the historic races.
Affirmative action, then, must become a special form of what is called
"race traitorism"--and not an individuated, voluntarist one (as one finds
in the work of Mills, for example), but a white-state-based traitorism.
The legal arguments for a Constitutionally based dismantling of white
property have been carefully and compellingly assembled in the 1990s by
scholars such as Ronald J. Fiscus, Cheryl I. Harris, and Barbara J.
Flagg, and this body of work is of great historico-theoretical
importance. One must underline, however, that this dismantling or
dissolving of that whole social construct called "race" need not and
should not become anything affirmative at all--such as, most clearly, an
affirmation of diversity. It is a spending that does not explicitly
produce new works, does not build anything, does not begin from the idea
of "humanity" or "diversity" in order to divest itself of privilege.
Such affirmative action does not have any concept in advance of "who"
will appear at the limit of such expenditure. In this sense, affirmative
action is neither action, in the sense of a positive project or
a building up of something, nor, strictly, affirmative of
anything, including constitutionalism itself. Indeed, such a version of
affirmative action would take one necessarily and theoretically to the
limits of U.S. constitutionalism and sovereignty in order to
confront its structurally embedded ruling class in the form of, for
example, a conception of citizenship as a work or a
labor that is judged or determined in terms of its
completeness. (In terms of the Japanese exclusion act cases, it was
precisely this citizen-structure that permitted the ascription of the
Japanese as foreign nationals, who had somehow not yet worked themselves
into the figure of "Americans." The question of the truth of matters of
Americanization is not at stake here, but merely the bare politico-social
scientific structure known as the "citizen.") This is simply to say that
rather than a process of reforming the U.S. Constitution (making it live
up to its best intentions), affirmative action at its limit necessarily
amounts to a dismembering of constitutionalism, to a "politics" at the
edge of
what Schmitt has called "the concept of the political" and toward, for
example, what Derrida has briefly described as "the State as it ought to
be--as a counter-institution, necessary for opposing those institutions
that represent particular interests and properties" (Derrida and Ferraris
51). Another way to say the preceding would begin with Schmitt's
definition of sovereignty as the exception and continue with Benjamin's
eighth thesis on the philosophy of history, Agamben's Homo
Sacer (1995), and Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri's
Empire (2000), all of which suggest in their different ways
that the exception has become the "rule" and that the modern state is
characterized by a permanent state of exception (Agamben, Homo
Sacer 12; Hardt and Negri 17-18). Such thought allows us to
conclude that, if sovereignty is the right to declare the exception, then
the limit of such sovereignty would be the exception to the
exception.[12] Transformative
affirmative action therefore will appear only at the limit of the
present juridical order (at the limit of white supremacy).
- This maximal form of affirmative action is
entirely faithful to our understanding of the Marxist project in general,
which, as Shershow suggests elsewhere, inaugurates a process of
calculation in order to end the regime of calculation (Shershow 491).
Affirmative action, if it is to be anything, will have to calculate
itself to the limits of its calculability--to the limit at which the
calculation and counting of a white privileged majority would have no
meaning. The promise of affirmative action will thus remain of interest
to political progressives strictly as a project that seeks to remove
"race" as a mode through which the state may distinguish and exclude.
- Affirmative action does not, however, take us to the
limit of all forms of exclusivity. For example, because affirmative
action begins and ends with the attempt to rationally allocate scarce
resources (contracts, tenure-track jobs, graduate student fellowships, and
the like), affirmative action remains complicit with the construction of
social and economic classes. One certainly could imagine a future world
in which the historic races no longer have meaning, yet in which the
opportunity to attend an Ivy League university instead of a community
college continues to be denied to some citizens. And even a policy of
guaranteed higher education for all might not in itself prevent some
educations from being (to borrow from George Orwell) "more equal than
others." Though "race" is an analytically distinct category from "class,"
their relationship remains overdetermined, and the attempt to address one
inevitably opens out onto the other (and onto still other domains of
inequity, such as gender, sexuality, and the like). In the next section
of this essay, we specifically take up another hotly debated policy matter
of recent years in order to explore the economic implications of
post-structuralist politics.
2. Towards a Theory of Welfare without Exclusion
- On the subject of welfare, candidates Bush and Gore in the last
presidential campaign didn't disagree even in the measured and ambiguous
way that they did on the subject of affirmative action. Rather, both
candidates hailed as a significant achievement the Personal
Responsibility and Work Opportunity Reconciliation Act passed by Congress
and signed by President Bill Clinton in 1996, an act that ended the very
idea of a federal entitlement to subsistence benefits and set strict
new limits on the amount of time a family could receive cash relief. In
fact, today it can easily seem as though practically everyone, on all
sides of the political spectrum, agrees that the constellation of
programs known loosely as "welfare"--especially the Aid for Families with
Dependent Children (AFDC)--had for a long time been promoting a so-called
"dependence" on the part of the poor.[13] This apparent political consensus about welfare
has somehow overcome what from another perspective might seem a broad and
fundamental ideological opposition. In this apparent opposition, one
side emphasizes a kind of altruism or mutual obligation ("we must help
those less fortunate than ourselves"), while the other side emphasizes a
kind of possessive individualism or self-reliance ("look out for number
one"; "charity begins at home"). Michael B. Katz, author of a history of
welfare policy in the United States, summarizes the enduring American
debate about welfare in almost exactly such terms: one side asks "what do
we owe each other, not simply as individuals, but as a community or
nation?" while the other side seeks to strengthen an "open market in
which responsible individuals [can] carve out their success or accept the
consequences of their failure" (Katz 332-3). The first of these
positions is typically thought of as liberal or Left, the second as
conservative or Right. We want to argue, however, that the prevailing
consensus about welfare is not simply the triumph of the conservative
position, but rather a kind of internal collapse of the opposition
itself, something that takes place at the conjunction of questions of
common being and the economic calculus.
- The thought of the Left seems to focus on the
first of these terms, grounding our social obligation in what Michael
Walzer, for example, calls our "membership" in a particular community, a
particular commonality of being. For Walzer, "the members of a political
community owe to one another... the communal provision of security and
welfare" (Walzer 63). The members of a community provide for one
another, and they do so precisely on the basis of their membership: the
immanent common being they share with other members.[14] This is a vision of communal inclusion
founded, in the most basic sense, on an exclusion, for members
of a community owe one another, as Walzer puts it, "mutual provision of
all those things for the sake of which they have separated themselves
from mankind as a whole" (65). And just as the communal membership
requires separation from and exclusion of other social subjects, so it
must involve an act of economic calculation. In other words, when we
ask, to whom are we obligated and why?, we must then also ask, how much
do we owe one another? how much can we afford to give? For further
example, the liberal economist Robert M. Solow, in his Tanner lectures at
Princeton University in 1998, begins by denouncing the so-called
"welfare-reform" bill of 1996 but nevertheless advocates a model of
welfare that (citing Amy Gutmann's introductory summary) "is guided by
two explicit aims: one, to increase self-reliance among those citizens
who are now on welfare, and two, to decrease the need for altruism among
those citizens who now pay for welfare" (viii). Altruism itself,
Solow concludes, "is scarce; there is never enough to go around" (3).
In such a model, social policies, even of the most "liberal" or
"progressive" kind, are literally constituted by acts of calculation, for
not only material resources but sociality itself is grasped as
being in short supply.
- Correspondingly, the conservative or right-wing
approach to social welfare, however much it seems to emphasize individual
responsibility and self-reliance instead of altruism or mutual
obligation, does not simply turn the other position inside-out to suggest
that we owe one another nothing. On the contrary, conservative
approaches to welfare envision an even more complex and subtle network of
mutual obligation.[15] In this case,
the connection of common being and the economic calculus is even more
fundamental, since what is believed most to unite us is our status as
economic subjects of a particular kind, whose behavior is the aggregate
product of a balance of needs and exertions, and who must accordingly be
constantly subjected to the goad of subsistence and survival. The basic
conservative position can thus be schematically summarized like this:
poverty occurs when individuals are either unable or unwilling to work.
When people are truly unable to work because of factors beyond
their control, such as a crippling disability, they are "deserving" of
economic support, and the community is obligated to give it. But more
often, people are merely unwilling to work, either because of
some moral weakness such as drug addiction or because they are just
plain lazy. In this case, it is argued, to relieve their poverty merely
rewards and encourages their moral failure and makes them dependent on
what more extreme ideologues like to call the "public trough."[16] Therefore, any system of organized
charity or welfare always tends to foster rather than alleviate poverty;
our moral obligation to prevent "undeserving" objects from receiving
relief is, if anything, even greater than our original obligation to
give.
- In recent years, this argument has been
expounded at length by an interrelated group of social scientists and
historians, including, among others, Martin Anderson, George Gilder,
Gertrude Himmelfarb, Lawrence M. Mead, Charles Murray, and Marvin
Olasky.[17] (The latter also coined
the slogan "compassionate conservatism" on which George W. Bush
successfully campaigned for president in 2000, a slogan that in this
context is revealed as referring specifically to the thesis just
summarized by denoting an alleged mode of proper compassion characterized
by its refusal to give to the "undeserving" poor. We will only cite one brief
example, since all these writers make essentially the same argument
and often cross-reference one another. Murray, in his introductory
remarks to one of Olasky's books, argues that even if our society went
far beyond all previous models of welfare relief and literally "put
everyone above the poverty line with a check," this would simply mean
that "families that once managed to stay above the poverty line through
their own labor" would begin "to take it a little easier," producing
"significant reductions in work effort." Therefore, to provide welfare
in the form of cash relief, Murray asserts, "is an efficient way to
increase the size of the underclass, not reduce it" (Murray, "Preface"
xiii-xiv).
- To compare these apparently opposed visions of
Left and Right is to see clearly how they merely propose what might be
called negative and positive versions of the same argument: the Right
emphasizes how a kind of naked and impersonal economic coercion forces
people to be self-reliant, and the Left emphasizes, instead, helping
people to help themselves... to be self-reliant. As Judith N. Shklar
suggests,
What is really astonishing is the degree of agreement between these
critics and defenders of welfare. Independence, exchanging the welfare
check for a paycheck, is what both sides hope for. All want to make good
citizens of the "underclass" by getting them a job and making them, too,
earning members of society. (96)[18]
And for either Left or Right, the seemingly inevitable claims of common
being, however such being is understood, always require an exclusion: we
will provide for our own, we will not relieve the "undeserving" poor, and
so on. And such observations also further indicate how, for Right and
Left alike, scarcity itself remains the one utterly irreducible
assumption, and therefore the economic calculus remains the one essential
and forever-unfinished operation of all social thought. It is here that
one rediscovers, on the axis of class, a version of the same formula we
previously uncovered on the axis of race. Just as the prevailing logic of
affirmation action can never go past the point where white privilege
senses its disturbance, so the prevailing logic of welfare can never
relieve poverty all the way down, to the point where economic privilege
itself might be threatened. Here, conventional liberal or conservative
approaches to the question of poverty converge in a kind of
aporia, an argument whose fatal circularity is hidden in plain
sight--precisely because its fundamental underlying assumption both
addresses and itself appears as what might be called
"nature," the ultimate otherness of material Necessity itself. People
require the goad of subsistence, it is argued, in order to keep them
working. And they must be kept working in order to subsist. Need keeps
us working and work overcomes our need. But this means that the one
absolute assumed in every version of this thought, subsistence itself, is
in effect something that cannot and must not be guaranteed. Our
daily victory over scarcity is the condition of our very existence and
also something that cannot be ensured in some political or social sense as
an expectation or a right. Subsistence itself must always be both present
and absent; for only the threat of its absence produces its presence. Or,
to phrase this ruinous argument in its most absolutely paradoxical form:
in order to overcome scarcity we must never overcome scarcity.
- This paradoxical and self-defeating logic, we go
on to argue, underlies a pair of interrelated Supreme Court decisions
that were issued about thirty years ago, but whose primary themes
continue to figure centrally in contemporary debates about welfare. At
the time of the first of these decisions, Shapiro v.
Thompson (1969), the Warren Court--now approaching its end
and already, of course, celebrated for its innovative decisions in civil
rights--had seemed to some observers to be on the brink of declaring a
constitutional "right" to economic subsistence, a hope that was, however,
effectively dashed the following year with Dandridge v.
Williams (1970).[19] In
Shapiro, the Court struck down durational residency
requirements in Connecticut and several other states, laws that required
a needy family to establish residence in a state for one full year before
becoming eligible for welfare benefits. In briefs submitted to the Court
on both sides of the case, it was acknowledged that such policies descend
from the so-called "poor laws" of Elizabethan England and early colonial
America, laws that prohibited indigent persons from leaving their own
parish and established draconian penalties for vagrancy.[20] For example, Robert K. Killian and Francis J.
MacGregor, attorneys general of Connecticut, acknowledge in their
appellant's brief that the central question of the case is
whether unlimited migration of those poor who do not want to enter the
labor market should be allowed, with the end result that Connecticut's
liberal program would be curtailed because of this additional tax bite,
or whether Connecticut should set up a reasonable residence requirement
that protected... those poor resident applicants, who in the past, had
contributed to the economy. (LBA 68: 10)
In other words, the appellants argue that durational residency
requirements are necessary to prevent indigents migrating to a state with
relatively higher benefits and hence putting pressure on that state's
welfare budget.
- The issues in this case thus locate themselves precisely
at the fatal intersection of common being and the economic calculus, for
there would be no dispute at all if there were not different levels of
welfare benefit in different American states. In effect, three different
levels of identity are at issue in this question: citizenship in a
particular state, citizenship in the United States, and membership in a
common humanity--this latter, in the discourse of this case, explicitly
understood as a mode of being characterized by particular needs and a
particular degree of willingness to work for the sake of the community
(or, as the appellants put it, to "contribute to the economy"). The
appellants defend residency requirements in the name of that social
calculation which all modes of common being seemingly make necessary and
by emphasizing the most particular mode of identity or common being at
issue. Killian and MacGregor concede that the state of Connecticut was,
in its laws, discriminating "against potential applicants [for welfare],
who come into the state... to get on the welfare rolls, and who would not
come into the state if there were no liberal welfare benefits" (LBA 68:
24); but stipulate that such discrimination is not "racially aimed" (LBA
68: 7) and is therefore not a "suspect" classification. Instead, the
classification is made only as part of a necessary process of quantitative
provision: that is, because "there is a practical limit to the amount of
tax dollars that can be raised" to provide for the "members" of the state
of Connecticut (LBA 68: 37). Correspondingly, another advocate for the
appellants, Lorna Lawhead Williams of Iowa, defended her state's similar
welfare residency laws during oral arguments as something made necessary
by the attempt to balance individual and communal needs. Williams claimed
that the distinction between residents and nonresidents is reasonable
because it affords the ones who want to have a sort of permanency in that
community and have the professionally hired counselors come into their
homes and help them on their family problems.... They help them. They
consult with them. They have a friend in the community, besides just
bread and butter money. (LBA 68: 339)
In this argument, it is made particularly clear how one must allegedly
exclude in order to include and must discriminate against outsiders in
order to maintain the intimacy of the community itself.
- Against such claims, Archibald Cox, representing
the appellees, moved the argument back towards broader modes of identity
and common being. He successfully convinced a majority of the court that
welfare residency requirements, precisely in their intended protection of
the integrity of individual state borders and budgets, infringed on a
constitutionally protected liberty: the right to travel. "Our
constitutional law," Cox writes in his brief for the case, "recognizes
the basic human right to geographic mobility," a liberty that "was a key
element in our development as a free people" (LBA 68: 100). (Cox even
points out, in a telling historical detail, that the Articles of
Confederation except "paupers and vagabonds" from what they otherwise
guaranteed to be "free ingress and regress to and from any other State,"
but that this exception was omitted in Article IV, Section 2 of the U.S.
Constitution, which declares that "the Citizens of each State shall be
entitled to all the Privileges and Immunities of Citizens in the several
States" [LBA 68: 100].) Cox also argues eloquently that the
classification at issue in this case
is made in relation to the bare essentials of life, material and
spiritual. Public assistance is the last resource of those unable to
support themselves.... For those who cannot satisfy the
one-year-residence rule, the classification means deprivation of shelter,
food, and clothing. When public assistance is withheld, the entire
quality of life--sometimes even life itself--is placed in jeopardy. (LBA
68: 92)
In effect, Cox's argument evokes a common human identity defined this
time not by its duties and responsibilities but by its brute material
needs. Thus, as he said in oral arguments, the policies in question
discriminate against "those who exercise the fundamental liberty of
moving to a new residence in pursuit of better opportunities, better
life, or what else they consider to be an advantage." Such a
discrimination, he argued strongly, "is invidious in the same sense that
discrimination on grounds of race or religion is invidious" (LBA 68:
390). Cox thus tried to associate a discrimination against short-time
residents with the kind of racial categories already recognized as
"suspect" classifications and therefore requiring a state to have
"compelling" reasons in order to employ them.
- Such arguments prevailed with the majority of
the court. In his decision, Justice William Brennan rejected the
communitarian language of insiders and outsiders and, echoing Cox's
language of biological necessity, argued that durational requirements
merely created
two classes of needy resident families indistinguishable from each other
except that one is composed of residents who have resided a year or more,
and the second of residents who have resided less than a year, in the
jurisdiction. On the basis of this sole difference, the first class is
granted, and the second class is denied, welfare aid upon which may
depend the ability of the families to obtain the very means to
subsist--food, shelter, and other necessities of life.... [The]
appellees' central contention is that the statutory prohibition of
benefits to residents of less than a year creates a classification which
constitutes an invidious discrimination denying them equal protection of
the laws. We agree. (Shapiro 627)
Citing Korematsu v. United States and the established
doctrine of "compelling" state interests, Brennan also argues that when
welfare applicants move from state to state, even if they are doing so to
seek higher welfare benefits, they are "exercising a constitutional
right, and any classification which serves to penalize the exercise of
that right, unless shown to be necessary to promote a compelling
governmental interest, is unconstitutional" (Shapiro 634).
For the majority, none of the several reasons proposed as justifications
for the state's interest in welfare residency requirements--such as
protecting state budgets or discouraging immigration by
indigents--appeared sufficiently compelling.
- Shapiro's rejection of durational
residency tests for welfare would thus seem to be a significant victory
for a relatively inclusive vision of welfare rights. But the logic of
this case actually conceals a theoretical limitation, at once
broad and particular, on the concept of collective provision.[21] As we have seen, Cox's successful
argument for the appellees emphasizes that residency requirements
infringe a constitutional right to travel and suggests that welfare is
different from other state-provided benefits because it addresses
fundamental human needs. In several exchanges during oral arguments,
however, Cox and the Court seem to indicate a crucial point at which the
provision of even such basic necessities can be limited. This limit is
never quite spelled out and yet is shadowed by the very reticence with
which Cox and the justices avoid spelling it out. This process begins
when Cox is in the process of questioning the various rationales that are
being used to explain the state's alleged interest in durational
residency requirements. One such argument is the idea that such
requirements provide an objective test of residence.[22] Cox suggests that "one has to be
very careful" about this concept, because
Residence under the Social Security laws means residence--means presence
in the state. Living there. Not for temporary purpose. In other words,
without the intention of going somewhere else. (LBA 68: 393)
Here, Cox seems at first to say that residence is no different than
simple presence, but then immediately begins to limit such a definition.
He concedes that residence must not be for a "temporary purpose" and
says there must be no intention to leave; yet he pointedly refrains from
the more obvious possible formulation: that residency requires a positive
intention to stay. The Court, perhaps understandably, wants to
know more about precisely what this means:
THE COURT. Suppose he wanted to stay in Massachusetts six months--live
as a resident?
MR. COX: He would then be a resident.
THE COURT. And live in Florida six months as a resident?
MR. COX: Well, it would then be--it's a little hard for me to think of
someone doing that and still qualifying for Aid to Dependent Children,
Your Honor. The very money spent going back and forth--
THE COURT: You can't laugh that proposition off, because that's a very
common thing in America.
MR. COX: Well, I suggest it isn't a common thing in relation to the
types of people we're talking about here. (LBA 68: 393)
Let us mark in passing the rather dark irony that surfaces momentarily
here in the acknowledgment that a political freedom to travel is not the
same thing as a material ability to travel. In 1956, Supreme Court
Justice Felix Frankfurter, in a concurring opinion on another case
involving issues of wealth and poverty, had cited Anatole France's
ironic praise of the "majestic equality" of a Law that "forbids the rich
as well as the poor to sleep under bridges, to beg in the streets, and to
steal bread" (Griffin v. Illinois 351 U.S. 12, 15). The
Shapiro decision in effect makes the same point in reverse,
by affirming how the law permits both rich and poor to spend six months
of the year in Florida if they can afford to get there. At this point,
however, the Court still wishes to press Cox on this difficult idea of
what it means to "live as a resident" in a state:
THE COURT: But how long must he be a resident?
MR. COX: Such a person under our position, to answer you squarely, such
a person under our position would be entitled to aid six months in
Massachusetts and six months in Florida....
THE COURT: That, Mr. Cox, is subject to the right of each state to take
a reasonable time to authenticate the bona fide residence in the state,
and the "means test," and the various other things.
MR. COX: Oh, yes, quite.... The point that I want to emphasize with
respect to this test of residence is that one must ask what is it that
you are trying to test? I think that it lurks behind that expression....
We are really asking more permanency than being in the state voluntarily
with no intention of leaving. And to the extent that something more
lurks there, then our answer is simply that requiring the "something
more" is itself an arbitrary and capricious classification. (LBA 68:
393-4)
Something "lurks" behind the demand for residency, Cox suggests--his very
image seeming, as it were, to evoke the homeless vagrant lurking in the
doorways and back alleys of civil life. Cox rejects whatever "lurks
behind" this demand for a so-called "permanency" that in some elusive
way transcends mere physical presence in the state. This term, Cox seems
to imply, is simply a coded expression for something that, in political
discourses of early-modern England and America, might have been called a
"settled interest," a minimum level of income or property (the kind of
criteria that used to be required, prior to and sometimes after the
American Constitution, even for suffrage itself).[23] Cox also rejects the idea argued in the
Connecticut brief that permanent residents are those who have made an
"investment" in the community, pointing out that AFDC is designed in the
first place to aid "dependent children," who can hardly be said to have
yet contributed anything to any community anywhere. Moreover, he says,
since it is generally impossible to "measure the matter of 'contribution'
or 'investment' in the community... this is really a euphemistic way of
expressing... discrimination against strangers, or outsiders" (LBA 68:
396). But the specific citizens discriminated against in this case (by
their exclusion from welfare benefits) are already being
considered, at least by Cox, as full-fledged residents. Does one then
cease to be a stranger and outsider at the very moment of arrival at a
given place, provided only that one has no "intention of going somewhere
else"? This question is necessarily pertinent in that this whole
exchange follows Cox's rejection of the idea that requiring a
one-year stay would provide the state with an "objective" test to
determine whether or not an individual was a genuine, bona fide
resident.
- But even as Cox systematically rejects all these
related ideas of permanency and economic interest as appropriate criteria
for welfare eligibility, he still accepts that there is some basic status
that can be called residency. In fact, he is constrained to do
so, for it is the heart of his argument--as Justice Brennan restates in
the passage from the majority decision cited above--that durational
welfare requirements do not merely distinguish between insiders and
outsiders, residents and nonresidents, but instead between two classes
of resident. But this "bona fide residence in a state" that both Cox and
the court agree is a legitimate distinction appears to be a deeply
problematic status, since it is constituted neither by simply
being in the state, nor by a particular duration of
time spent there, nor by having a "settled interest" of property and
income. A radical indeterminacy seems to be inscribed not only in this
all-important concept but also in the parallel idea of travel and
migration against which residency must be defined. A few moments later,
in fact, the Court draws from Cox another significant qualification:
THE COURT: I haven't quite understood how all the arguments are going on
the assumption that the right to travel from place to place is precisely
the same as the right to live where you please.
MR. COX: Well I think that I have sought to stress the right to live
where you please as the basic right. It seems to me that the right to
journey, to make a pleasure swing around the country or to go to Europe,
raises different problems and is a lesser right, I would think. And my
case--Your Honors emphasized a point I should have made more sharply,
perhaps. Our case deals with the right to live where you please to seek
better opportunities.
THE COURT: That's what I think this resolves itself into, instead of the
right to "travel."
MR. COX: I agree. (LBA 68: 397)
Even though the salient issue of Shapiro is repeatedly
defined as the right to travel, the case would indeed seem, as
Cox concedes here, to be more precisely understood as being about the
right to migrate, to "live where you please to seek better
opportunities." This more specific word does briefly appear in the
majority decision:
An indigent who desires to migrate, resettle, find a new job,
and start a new life will doubtless hesitate if he knows that he must
risk making the move without the possibility of falling back on state
welfare assistance during his first year of residence, when his need may
be most acute. But the purpose of inhibiting migration by needy
persons into the State is constitutionally impermissible.
(Shapiro 629; emphases added)
In this passage, migration refers to the act of a person who goes
somewhere to settle or make a life: the act of the pioneer, the
homesteader, or the immigrant, the very dramatis personae of the
American dream. In many respects, the appellees' winning case depends on
the ideological force of this image, as against an equally ideological
contrast between the homeless vagrant and what the Court calls the "old
families" of a well-established community (401). In his majority
decision, for example, Brennan argues that residency requirements are
grounded in the assumption "that indigents who enter a State with the
hope of securing higher welfare benefits are somehow less deserving." By
contrast, Brennan writes,
we do not perceive why a mother who is seeking to make a new life for
herself and her children should be regarded as less deserving because she
considers, among other factors, the level of a State's public assistance.
Surely such a mother is no less deserving than a mother who moves into a
particular State in order to take advantage of its better educational
facilities. (Shapiro 631-2)
In such a passage, Brennan in effect displaces the ideological specters
of the "welfare queen" and the "lurking" vagrant by imagining the kind of
person at issue in this case as a devoted mother moved by a spirit of
independence and rational economic calculation to seek out a better life
for her family and herself. The force of the image is almost enough to
conceal how this description also implicitly accepts the conservative
principle that relief should, in any case, go only to what Brennan
frankly calls the "deserving" poor.
- Nevertheless, the word "migrant"
inevitably evokes another meaning that indicates the absolute limit of
what might be thinkable by the prevailing logic of welfare. This becomes
clear in another exchange a few minutes later:
THE COURT: Mr. Cox, I've come across statements to the effect that in
some of these states that have fine climates, such as the far Western
states, the children of migrants are not allowed into the public schools
because they don't satisfy the residence requirements; and also the same
sort of statement with respect to access to state health facilities.
Assuming that that's so, does that present a related conceptual problem?
MR. COX: Well I would think the genuine migrant presented a different
problem, that here we are talking about someone who is not moving from
place to place. I don't mean to suggest, Your Honor, that there isn't
ground for a constitutional attack in those cases, but I do suggest that
at least from the standpoint of what we're dealing with--
THE COURT: But a negative answer here--would a negative answer here
indicate, a fortiori, a negative answer in--
MR. COX: You mean if we were to lose these cases?
THE COURT: If you were to lose these cases, would that indicate a
negative answer in the case of the migrants who are denied an opportunity
to go to school?
MR. COX: I would think it clearly would even enable Connecticut, say, to
say that it would not admit to the schools in Greenwich and other places
near New York the children of people who move out from New York to
Greenwich because there are better schools there (403).
This striking passage both insists on and yet virtually refuses to name
or consider the migrant worker as the limit case at which the whole
argument finally arrives. The force of the discourse in the current case
tends to exclude the migrant from consideration, by focusing on residents
who are said to be equal in status and therefore entitled to "equal
protection" under the law. Yet the figure of the migrant worker forces
itself into the argument here, much as it did implicitly in Cox's
previous reference above to "strangers" and "outsiders." The Court seems
to ask, though perhaps not very clearly and with a kind of reticence,
about the implications of the current case for the much more drastic
residency restrictions imposed on migrant workers, who are often, as he
mentions, excluded from even the most basic state services such as
elementary education because they lack even the intention to
stay in the place they happen to be. If the Court should decide in this
case to allow states to deny welfare benefits even to immigrants
in the positive sense (those who arrive intending to stay), then states
will surely believe they can deny services of any kind to the mere
migrant. Cox assents to this conclusion, though only in the
most indirect of ways: by displacing the already-ghostly figure of the
migrant worker with that of the citizen who moves from the city to the
suburbs because they have better schools there! One suspects that Cox's
incongruous counterexample is intended to reassure the Court that more
is at stake here than the rights of those whom even that tenuous and
indefinable status of "resident" eludes. At any rate, one thing is clear
about the decision reached in this case. Although it is still commonly
argued that "Residency as a factor in determining eligibility for public
assistance was declared illegal... in the case of Shapiro v.
Thompson (Trattner 21, n. 3), the real fact is, as Edward Sparer
summarizes, that "Shapiro bans durational residency
tests, but not residency tests." The decision thus permits the
states to "bar the nonresident citizen from receiving welfare benefits,"
and "the principal group of persons to whom this distinction applies is
the migratory workers who move from state to state for the purpose of
working in the field" (76). The migrant worker is thus a kind of
absent presence in a case whose specific positive effect--the striking
down of durational requirements for AFDC--seems in its whole force and
absolute principle to license his exclusion from social welfare in every
sense. Even more broadly, this case affirms certain rights and
freedoms only by limiting them and extends welfare benefits to
newly arrived residents only by excluding the nonresident.
- Such conclusions are further confirmed by the
obvious observation that the figure of the illegal alien or migrant
worker, present in this case only in his nearly total absence, is by
contrast central in other discourses about welfare. To cite an almost
random example of an all-too-familiar discourse, Senator Strom Thurmond,
a few years before the welfare reform bill of 1996, made the argument
that such a bill would be necessary
to limit the rising tide of illegal aliens who, attracted by the many
advantages of living or working in the United States, flood across our
borders and take jobs from American workers. In many cases, those
illegal entrants and their families soon become a welfare burden on our
society, supported in one way or another by the American taxpayer.
(qtd. in Harris 186)
Correspondingly, the "welfare reform" act of 1996 placed explicit new
limits on what it also carefully identifies as three different kinds of
migrant or immigrant: Americans moving between states, "qualified" (that
is, legal) aliens from outside the United States, and illegal aliens. For
the first class, the bill authorized any State to "apply to a family the
rules (including benefit amounts) of the program... of another State if
the family has moved to the State from the other State and has resided in
the State for less than 12 months" (United States 20).[24] The second class, qualified aliens, were declared
"not eligible for any Federal means-tested public benefit for a period of
5 years beginning on the date of the alien's entry into the United States"
(United States 161). And as for the third class, which would, of course,
include the majority of migrant workers, the law provides that "an alien
who is not a qualified alien... is not eligible for any Federal public
benefit" (United States 157). In the debates leading up to and following
the passage of the bill, some liberal voices particularly deplored such
provisions, and President Clinton promised that "if reelected he would fix
a flawed welfare law" (Weaver 336)--though this promise (unlike his famous
original promise to "end welfare as we know it") was at best partially
fulfilled by provisions of the 1997 budget, which restored some benefits
for disabled immigrants. And in any case, it was merely the restrictions
on welfare for legal aliens that were even at issue. Our analysis
suggests, by contrast, that limitations on welfare for "strangers and
outsiders" are in no sense merely peripheral to the bill's overall purpose
but rather quite central to it. Indeed, the fact that, as most studies
suggest, illegal migrant workers pay more into state budgets (via
payroll taxes) than they ever receive via welfare also merely confirms, by
contrast, that such policies do not really respond to material social
problems but emerge, rather, from the kind of enduring habits of thought
sketched here.
- Early in the year following
Shapiro, the Supreme Court issued another decision on
welfare that is, by contrast, generally considered a profound defeat for
welfare rights. In Dandridge v. Williams (1970), the Court
upheld the constitutionality of laws in Maryland (and, by extension, of
numerous similar laws in other states) that set a maximum cap on the
welfare benefits available to a given family. In Maryland, specific
welfare benefits were paid to each needy family under AFDC according to a
formula calculating the minimum level of subsistence income necessary per
child; yet the state also set a maximum limit of $250 per month per
family and thus failed to provide additional benefits for any family with
seven or more members--five children with two parents, or six children
with one parent. Like Shapiro, this case thus also locates
itself at the intersection of common being and the economic calculus. In
this case, it is implicitly conceded by both sides that human beings are
united by a common level of material and financial need that can be
precisely determined by the state. There could have been be no dispute
at all if there had not been that initial act of calculation by the state
to determine the minimum subsistence level for a family of three, four,
or five people, and so forth.
- At the simplest level, then, the Court's
decision is a negative one: that is, it rules that a state need not
support people according to the state's own calculation of their needs.
Such a conclusion is, moreover, itself made in the name of calculation.
As Justice Potter Stewart writes in the majority decision, the Maryland
law is justified as an attempt to "reconcile the demands of its needy
citizens with the finite resources available to meet those demands"
(Dandridge 474). Cutting off the larger families from
additional benefits is one reasonable way, the majority argues, of
rationing an overall welfare budget that is evidently too small to meet
the needs of collective provision in the state. At the end of the
majority decision, Justice Stewart once again portrays the Court's
actions in negative terms: as simply a refusal to intervene in matters
best left to the wisdom of state lawmakers:
We do not decide today that the Maryland regulation is wise, that it best
fulfills the relevant social and economic objectives that Maryland might
ideally espouse, or that a more just and humane system could not be
devised. Conflicting claims of morality and intelligence are raised by
opponents and proponents of almost every measure, certainly including the
one before us. But the intractable economic, social, and even
philosophical problems presented by public welfare assistance programs
are not the business of this Court. (Dandridge 486)
In fact, however, the negative form of the principle affirmed in this
decision necessarily entails a positive version of itself, one that indeed
has fundamental economic, social, and philosophic consequences.
This positive principle might be formulated something like this: the
State must calculate a standard of material need for its
citizens and yet must not meet that standard. The brief for the
appellants frankly acknowledges that the laws at issue here continue to
reflect long-standing fears about the "undeserving poor," citing the
conclusions of the British Poor Law Commission of 1835 that the situation
of people on relief "shall not be made really or apparently so eligible
(desirable) as the situation of the independent laborer of the lowest
class" (LBA 69: 60). They also cite Arthur Burns, at the time a
counselor to President Nixon on domestic affairs and soon to be Chair of
the Federal Reserve bank, who claims that "there are... States in which
the welfare payments going to the family are larger than what an
unskilled man working at or close to the minimum wage can earn," which
"stimulates some people to leave work and join the welfare population."
To avoid this, Burns argues, the state should set "a maximum on welfare
payments so that welfare is not too attractive financially" (cited LBA
69: 87). This argument, which prevailed with a majority of the Court on
this occasion, and which we identified above as the quintessential
right-wing approach to poverty, here grounds itself in an act of
calculation that is always unfinished (that is, the state must calculate
the minimum it should give and then must also recalculate how much
not to give) and, even more paradoxically, grasps equality
itself only in the form of inequality. In its laws, argued the
majority decision, "the State maintains some semblance of an equitable
balance between families on welfare and those supported by an employed
breadwinner" (Dandridge 486). But what the Court means, to
speak in coldly practical terms, is that welfare families must have
less than the working poor: the "equitable balance" of which he
speaks literally exists in the form of a material inequity. To
be as clear as possible, in this case, the law devotes itself with its
full force and principle not to ending privation, and not even,
at least after a certain point, to relieving privation, but
instead, quite precisely, to preserving it.
- This paradoxical logic only deepens when one
considers the appellees's unsuccessful argument that family caps for
welfare infringe on the constitutional doctrine of Equal Protection. The
maximum grant regulation, write Joseph A. Matera and Gerald A. Smith in
their appellee's brief, creates "two subclasses of AFDC recipients, those
who are members of large families containing seven or more people and
those who belong to families of six members or less" (LBA 69: 125). And
as for the additional children in large families, Matera suggests in oral
argument, "the State computes their needs, and then simply ignores them"
(LBA 69: 298). The Court points out, however, that the state formula
does not simply provide a particular dollar amount per child but rather
employs a sliding scale, giving "$30 a month for the first child, and $25
a month for the second child" and so forth (LBA 69: 300). It would thus
seem difficult to make an equal protection argument in terms of
individual children within families, as opposed to between
families as a whole. To be sure, the state makes its initial calculation
on the basis of the number of children in a family. But, as the Court
suggests:
THE COURT: ...$30 isn't allocated to A, and $10 to B, or anything like
that?
MR. MATERA: No, sir. It's dependent upon the number of individuals in
the family.
THE COURT: So, when the State sets a maximum of $250, that money is
allocable among all members of the family. It doesn't mean that the
State doesn't think the seventh child is going to not share at all in the
$250.
MR. MATERA: I would disagree, in this respect, Mr. Justice White,
because the State does think that.... Because when they looked at... the
number of people in that family, they said that in order to live you need
$331--
THE COURT: Well, I understand that.
MR. MATERA: ...But, of course, the welfare department would believe that
the mother would take those funds which already are available, and
certainly divide them among the children, because she wouldn't allow
certain children to starve merely because their needs are not recognized,
you see. (LBA 69: 305)
And again, similarly, in the final moments of the oral arguments:
THE COURT: ...it's not the fifth, or sixth, or seventh, or eighth child
that necessarily suffers. It's the whole family's income that is
reduced, on a per capita basis.
MR. MATERA: That would be the practical effect, because a parent would
simply not let its child starve. (LBA 69: 310)
At this point, it is hard not to hear a hypothetical rejoinder that
Matera's words seem irresistibly to evoke: that although a parent would
simply not let its child starve, a state would. To be precise, however,
the Court is simply claiming that because of the possible economies of
scale and, even more so, the emotional bonds of the family as such, the
"fifth or sixth child in a family" will "eat right along with the rest of
them," so that the law "just means that everybody [in the family] would
eat less" (306). As the majority decision puts it, more formally:
Although the appellees argue that the younger and more recently arrived
children in such families are totally deprived of aid, a more realistic
view is that the lot of the entire family is diminished because of the
presence of additional children without any increase in payments.
(Dandridge 477)
Thus, as it were, the additional children are not entitled to a claim of
equal protection under the law precisely because they belong to a
collectivity: they are members of a kind of mini-community within which
they will be provided for, if not adequately, then at least
equally with all its other members.
- Our primary point here is not that this claim
about the intrinsic equality of the family is spurious, as a whole range
of feminist work on familial relations and domestic abuse has vividly
suggested. Nor are we primarily observing that these so-called "family
caps" on welfare (which remain central in contemporary debates on the
subject) are obviously conditioned by the ideological fantasy of the
"welfare queen" who has additional babies in order to get larger
welfare checks. Rather, we want to emphasize how this decision grounds
itself on the alleged existence of this domain of absolute, unconditional
collectivity and equality, the family, which it uses to license or
justify a vision of society and the state understood as, by contrast,
fundamentally individualistic and unequal. Within this logic, the family
is assumed, by some mysterious and nonnegotiable necessity of its own
nature, to care for each new member within its preexisting material
capabilities, however limited they may be. The whole purpose of the AFDC
program from its beginnings, the appellees argue repeatedly in the
discourse of this case, is to "make it possible for the child to remain
in or return to the custody and care of his parents or relatives who have
a natural bond of affection and concern for his well-being" (LBA 69: 45;
paraphrasing the Social Security Act, 42 U.S.C.A. 601). Indeed, the
appellees observe how the Maryland Code itself declares that the
primary goal of AFDC is "the strengthening of family life" (LBA
69: 135, citing Maryland Code Annotated Article 88A, Section 44a
[1064]). Only via the achievement of this goal does the program in any
sense even attempt to achieve what might otherwise be understood as the
broader and more fundamental goal of enabling "the child's unmet need to
be supplied" (LBA 69: 45). The welfare reform bill of 1996 operates with
precisely the same logic. This bill amends Title IV of the Social
Security Act in a fundamental way: on the one hand, it continues to state
that the fundamental purpose of welfare is to "encourage the formation
and maintenance of two-parent families," and on the other hand, it
specifically licenses states to enact "family cap" limits on welfare and
stipulates that its programs will not "entitle any individual or family
to assistance" (42 USCS 601 [2001]). So, one more time, let us be
plain: precisely as it strips away any protection against scarcity from
almost every space of social life, the law also claims to be fostering a
specific domain of irreducible collectivity called "the family" within
which, allegedly, our most fundamental needs may somehow always be met.
3. At the Limits of Community
- The two figures our readings have discovered at the center of
these cases about welfare, the migrant worker and the family, represent
as it were the positive and negative limits of common being itself. The
migrant worker is excluded from the process of mutual provision in the
familiar positive way, because of his race, his national identity, his
lack of a settled interest or even a permanent residency in a place. With
the family, however--or at least with this hypothetical vision of the
family--the very idea of common being encounters something that exceeds
it: that is, our national identity as Americans binds us less
than this imagined family does. Thus, even as our analysis pointed to a
theoretical exclusion of the migrant at the heart of the
seemingly inclusive logic of the Shapiro decision, so the
brutal language of indifference in Dandridge could also be
read as announcing the possibility of something very different: a sphere
of limitless, open-ended inclusivity, where all, as the Court suggests,
will "eat right along with the rest." In this imagined collectivity,
mutual provision evidently takes place without thought; or, more
precisely, takes place via a calculation that, instead of being
forever-unfinished, is rather always-already in excess of itself. And to
do no more than extend the same hypothetical model in the other
direction, every kind of abundance would, one can only assume, be
similarly shared without thought or calculation--or, again, more
precisely, shared via a process of calculation that undoes itself by
being shared.
- In this case, indeed, the brute fact that real
families do not necessarily embody this model is precisely what allows it
to reemerge as a new possibility in theory and in practice. For this is
not, of course, to suggest that a state should think of itself as one big
happy family, a model long ago contaminated with the worst features of
patriarchal oppression. It is, rather, to suggest that at one and the
same point where a model of community based on common being
reaches its negative limit, one recognizes, by contrast, what Jean-Luc
Nancy in The Inoperative Community calls the community of our
being-in-common. The various models of mutual
provision considered throughout, whether in relatively liberal,
communitarian versions, or relatively conservative or libertarian
versions, grasp community only as a unity of subjects who have
something in common and whose obligation to other members
always retains a fatal circularity: each subject is obligated to help
create and preserve other subjects who are themselves defined by their
capacity and willingness to undertake the same obligation. In such a
model, as we have observed, the community does not and cannot end
privation or poverty, since the threat of these things constitutes not
only what is understood as the necessary goad of survival, but indeed
the very glue of the social bond itself. In the community for which we
argue, by contrast, singular beings join together on the basis of having
nothing in common, that is, they have in common only their own
finitude and consequently their exposure to both scarcity and to one
another. Here, the inescapable neediness of finite beings is grasped not
as their weakness or reproach but as their access to a collective wealth
that is, if not infinite, then at least without limit. As
against what even progressives tend to suggest is a necessary
conservation of altruism (e.g., Solow ix), the community of
being-in-common begins in the recognition of what Emmanuel Levinas calls
the "plenitude of alterity": a relation to the Other that is
incommensurable and that therefore exceeds all calculation (Levinas
345). This community has no inside or outside and therefore no insiders
or outsiders; it is a community (and an economy) of an all
that remains forever open, an all thought so radically that this
word would no longer even be an appropriate term to calculate it.
- Here, similarly, the very idea of "welfare"
shifts--rather as T. H. Marshall suggested over thirty years ago but
exceeding his suggestion--from its negative to its positive sense, from
the ideas of "relief" or "insurance" or "safety net" to the much broader
and more basic semantic idea of well-being. Marshall argues that the
provision of welfare in this sense to everyone cannot exactly be a legal
right as such, precisely because such a right would have to be calculated,
quantified, and legislated; instead, he suggests, it can only be provided
via what he calls "discretion," an operation that does not ask, "'what do
the regulations say must be done?', but 'What action is most likely to
produce the desired result?'" (87-88). And, he goes on, "this notion of
discretion as positive, personal and beneficent can only be fully realized
in a 'welfare society', that is, a society that recognizes its collective
responsibility to seek to achieve welfare, and not only to relieve
destitution or eradicate penury" (88). Marshall's own thought
unfortunately also illustrates how easy it is for this discretion to
simply become calculation by another name.[25] Thus one must give a slight additional turn to his
schema, understanding this "discretion" as something always performed in
the name of what Derrida calls Justice: that which brings forth and yet
always escapes and exceeds all notions of law and right. "It is just that
there be law," Derrida argues, but at the same time, "just justice is
incalculable, it requires us to calculate with the incalculable" ("Force
of Law" 16). And the evident fact that justice "is always in excess with
respect to right" does not mean, as some might claim (attempting, in the
familiar way, to reduce deconstruction to quietism), that justice is
therefore infinitely deferred or simply unattainable. Rather, as Derrida
always insists, this "excess" whose name is Justice "presses
urgently here and now" (Derrida and Ferraris 23).
- It is therefore self-evident to us that just as
affirmative action makes sense only in the name of absolute
deracialization, so any law addressing something called "welfare" must
guarantee income, education, health-care, and the like, to all social
subjects; and that the sole criterion of eligibility for such guarantees
can only be finite being itself. Therefore: no one who is in any sense
there can possibly be excluded from it. This process of mutual
provision cannot even be reduced to what has sometimes been called a
guaranteed minimum income (a formulation that simply returns to the
economic calculus in its most ruinous form).[26] Indeed, what some would raise as objections to such
a policy--that the level of such guaranteed income could not be determined
in advance nor fixed once and for all, that people could and probably
would always ask for it to be higher, and that to afford it would
collectively require the expenditure without reserve of all economic
privilege and individual wealth--are in fact its strengths. For one must
understand this worldwide offering or sharing of well-being as, to repeat
our formula, a process of calculation intended to undo calculation.
Because all being is being-in-common, and because all community takes
place, as Nancy argues, at the common limit where finite beings are
exposed to one another, therefore those of us who meet at this limit (of)
community literally in so doing pro-vide or look out for one
another. This is not a (moral) choice, nor the product of ascetic
self-denial, nor even something to be built as a Work in the aftermath of
a revolution and in the name of some principle like Humanity or Equality;
rather, it is the simple, inevitable (practical) condition of our
existence, remaining always already to be re-revealed.
- Some will perhaps respond, however, that this
essay, far from having in any sense begun to solve the problem
of the practical, has not yet even begun to address it; that all this
remains mere theory, and that none of it is either feasible or
realistic. People will simply not go along with it, some will say;
indeed, Americans have recently shown, if anything, an increasing
resistance to affirmative action and an "increasing reluctance... to
support citizens on welfare" (Gutmann ix). But we observe how such
objections are always themselves posed as questions of thought
and yet never really presented as one's own thought. In other
words, it is not argued that racial or economic justice is somehow
materially impossible; rather, it is alleged that there is some
ideality, some unspecified absence or vague presence in consciousness
that makes it impossible. Similarly, most people never quite say, "I am
selfish"; instead, they say, impersonally or abstractly, that altruism is
scarce, or that Americans are greedy and individualistic, or that life
isn't fair. The same logic always re-engenders itself: because there
might not be enough, we must each grab what we can, producing an
aggregate of selfishness that endlessly ensures the repetition of the
same scarcity and the same response. But if the impediment itself exists
only in ideas and consciousness, then where else but in what Nancy calls
"the gravity of thought" could one look for the solution?[27] Thus the whole question of the practical
necessarily evokes that exhilarating inversion that Marx articulates in
perhaps his most famous single utterance--"Philosophers have only
interpreted the world, in various ways; the point, however, is
to change it" (Marx and Engels 145). We join others in the broad Marxist
and post-Marxist tradition in understanding this famous dictum not as a
simple opposition of theory and practice, intended to reproach
philosophers for interpreting rather than changing the world. Rather,
Marx suggests that to reinterpret the world is always, and necessarily,
to change it.[28] We acknowledge,
then, that our project here is unfinished, but this is because the
community for which we argue is always "to come" and because the problem
of the practical itself therefore always remains (to be)
thought.
Department of English
Michigan State University
smichael@pilot.msu.edu
Department of English
Miami University
shershsc@muohio.edu
COPYRIGHT (c) 2002 SCOTT MICHAELSEN AND SCOTT
CUTLER SHERSHOW. READERS MAY USE
PORTIONS OF THIS WORK IN ACCORDANCE WITH THE FAIR USE PROVISIONS OF U.S.
COPYRIGHT LAW. IN ADDITION, SUBSCRIBERS AND MEMBERS OF SUBSCRIBED
INSTITUTIONS MAY
USE THE ENTIRE WORK FOR ANY INTERNAL NONCOMMERCIAL PURPOSE BUT, OTHER THAN
ONE COPY SENT BY EMAIL, PRINT OR FAX TO ONE PERSON AT ANOTHER LOCATION FOR
THAT INDIVIDUAL'S PERSONAL USE, DISTRIBUTION OF THIS ARTICLE OUTSIDE OF A
SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION FROM EITHER THE
AUTHOR OR THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS IS EXPRESSLY FORBIDDEN.
THIS ARTICLE AND OTHER CONTENTS OF THIS ISSUE ARE
AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE UNTIL RELEASE OF THE NEXT ISSUE. A
TEXT-ONLY ARCHIVE OF THE JOURNAL IS ALSO AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE.
FOR FULL HYPERTEXT ACCESS TO BACK ISSUES, SEARCH UTILITIES, AND OTHER
VALUABLE FEATURES, YOU OR YOUR INSTITUTION MAY SUBSCRIBE TO
PROJECT MUSE, THE
ON-LINE JOURNALS PROJECT OF THE
JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS.
Notes
1. See Derrida, "Racism's Last Word"
(1985), and Derrida and Tlili, eds., For Nelson Mandela (1987).
2. The model of politics and
collectivity for which we argue in this essay follows most closely the
thought of Jean-Luc Nancy in The Inoperative Community. In
addition to the works named in our text, other books that have influenced
our thought include Maurice Blanchot's The Unavowable
Community and Giorgio Agamben's The Coming
Community. We also believe the community for which we argue to be
broadly consistent with what Derrida calls "the new international" in
Specters of Marx. Although Derrida has expressed
theoretical reservations about the term "community," he also acknowledges
that he finally has "no qualms" about "Blanchot's 'unavowable' community
or Nancy's 'inoperative' one" (Derrida and Ferraris 24). We join
Derrida in understanding Nancy, as well as Blanchot, as affirming "a
communism where the common is anything but common; it is the placing in
common [mise en commun] of that which is no longer of the order
of subjectivities, or of intersubjectivity as a relation--however
paradoxical--between presences." It is important to emphasize,
therefore, how the thought of any of these writers always seeks to
question "community in the classical sense, and intersubjectivity as
well" (Derrida and Ferraris 24-25).
3. See the volume co-edited by
Guinier and Sturm, and perhaps in particular Claude M. Steele's
contribution, "Understanding the Performance Gap" (60-67), on the problem
of what he calls "stereotype threat." During the period in which this
article was written, the head of the University of California school
system, Richard C. Atkinson, announced plans to "no longer require that
students take the SAT I in order to apply for admission to the
University," in part because "minority perceptions about fairness [of
such tests] cannot be... easily dismissed." Atkinson's remarks
can be found at the following address: <http://www.ucop.edu/ucophome/pres/comments/satspch.html>.
4. The other Justices who side with
Powell, it should be noted, assert in their opinion a strict construction
of Title VI, for example. The matter of revised or even reversed
construction principles over time is interesting, to say the least.
5. Reva B. Siegel's exemplary analysis
of Hopwood argues that "strict scrutiny" doctrines under the
Fourteenth Amendment radically restrict the use of race-conscious
remedies "in order to protect and preserve real differences among racial
groups" (49). See Gotanda and also Kull, who both suggest that
U.S. constitutional policy has never been "color blind."
6. See Personal Justice Denied:
The Report of the Commission on
Wartime Relocation and Internment of Civilians (Washington, D.C.:
Government Printing Office, 1982). The most salient parts of the document,
including the quotation, are on the web at:
<http://www.geocities.com/capitolhill/Senate/4417/personaljusticedenied.html>.
7. Statistics in this paragraph are
from the University's official Affirmative Action Reports, issued in
October 2000, produced by the Office of the Assistant Provost and
Assistant Vice President for Academic Human Resources. The quotation is
from the University's UAAO, Paulette Granberry Russell, from an e-mail,
25 January 2001. The University does provide itself some "wiggle room"
on these matters, since it does break down particular minority
utilizations/underutilizations separately from the general minority
statistic. Nevertheless, every possible category of minority hiring for
the Department of English is listed as having a hiring goal of zero,
which effectively tells Chairs of Departments that no affirmative action
activity is necessary. The concept of "availability" is defined on the
University's Affirmative Action Office website as: "Availability analysis
estimates the percentages of minorities and women available for
employment in each identified job group. Persons available are those
interested and qualified to perform the work at hand during the upcoming
Affirmative Action Plan year." Michigan State University's policies on
affirmative action are contained in two documents called "IDEA" and "IDEA
II." "IDEA II" specifically links University support of affirmative
action to "utilization" data: "Academic units that are
underrepresented in terms of relevant availability data can work in
partnership with the Office of the Provost as needed to arrange
transitional funding and/or set up funds necessary to take advantage of
targeted hiring opportunities when they arise, or to broaden possible
recruitment or retention activities" (emphasis added; <http://web.msu.edu/access/idea2.html#enhanceeffort>).
8. Delgado has written about "role
model" theory in telling ways ("Affirmative"). This logic, too,
would have proven problematic, had the Supreme Court affirmed it.
9. See the Grutter
companion decision, decided 27 March 2001, which overturns the
University of Michigan Law School system of affirmative action
admissions and explicitly sets up a future collision of
Gratz and Grutter on appeal.
10. It is important to
acknowledge here and throughout (as general inspiration for the analysis
of affirmative action in these pages) the significance of Girardeau A.
Spann's work in this area, and particularly Race Against the
Court, which concludes that racial minorities must recognize the
Supreme Court as having functioned generally as "an antagonistic political
institution rather than as a hospitable benefactor" (170).
11. See, for example, Klinkner and Smith
for an elaboration of the limits of twentieth-century racial inequity
reformism.
12.
We borrow the phrase "exception to
the exception" from Donald E. Pease, in his oral response to Michael
Hardt at Michigan State University's "Globalicities" conference, October,
2001.
13. Nancy Fraser and Linda Gordon
suggest that "'dependency' is the single most crucial term in the current
U. S. debate about welfare reform," in an important essay that
historicizes and critiques this term (618).
14. In addition to books otherwise
cited, some of the many other outstanding liberal or Left approaches to
welfare include Frances Fox Piven and Richard A. Cloward's
Regulating the Poor (1971; 2nd ed. 1993); Michael B. Katz's
The Undeserving Poor (1989); Joel F. Handler's and Yeheskel
Hansenfeld's The Moral Construction of Poverty (1991) and
Handler's The Poverty of Welfare Reform (1995); Linda
Gordon's Pitied but Not Entitled (1994); Herbert Gans's
The War Against the Poor (1995); and Ruth Sidel's
Keeping Women and Children Last (1996).
15.
Mead argues quite specifically
that "obligation," rather than mere quantitative "equality," is the
fundamental issue of all social policy, arguing that "The most vulnerable
Americans need obligations, as much as rights" (Mead 17).
16. Senator Jesse Helms
on the floor of the Senate on Thursday, 1 August 1996, alleged that "the
average welfare recipient stays at the public trough for 13 years."
(Helms's statistics are, by the way, as excessive as his rhetoric, since,
as Wilson documents, most studies of welfare usage conclude that "half of
all welfare recipients exited welfare during the first year, and
three-quarters departed within two years" (166).
17. Some of the best-known works in
this conservative conversation are Martin Anderson's Welfare
(1978), George Gilder's Wealth and Poverty (1981), Charles
Murray's Losing Ground (1984), Lawrence M. Mead's
Beyond Entitlement (1986), Gertrude Himmelfarb's The
De-Moralization of Society (1995), and Marvin Olasky's The
Tragedy of American Compassion (1996). Concise samples of various
writers making the argument summarized here can be found in Mehuron,
Points of Light (1990).
18. William Julius Wilson agrees that
"a liberal-conservative consensus on welfare reform has recently
emerged," which includes, among other things, the opinion that welfare
recipients should be required to work (164).
19. Edward V. Sparer, who at the time
of these decisions headed the Columbia University Center on Social
Welfare Policy and Law, writes that "the particulars in the Court's
reasoning... gave great hope that Shapiro would have
enormous consequences for other welfare rights. By April 1970... the
Court--after a significant change in personnel--made it clear that such
hope was false" (75).
20. See, e.g., Kurland and Casper,
Landmark Briefs and Arguments of the Supreme Court (37,
108, 237). All subsequent citations from the briefs and oral arguments
of both Shapiro v. Thompson and Dandridge v.
Williams are from this series, henceforth identified
parenthetically as LBA, with volume and page number.
21. Although it has different
particulars, our argument about Shapiro is complementary to
that of Bussiere, who suggests that Justice Brennan put together a
majority decision in this case only by grounding it "in the right to
interstate travel and... classical liberal values," thus stripping the
case "of its downwardly redistributive policy potential" (107). We
also agree generally with Nixon, who argues "that the Supreme
Court's traditional approach to deciding durational residency
requirements, while producing a sound moral outcome, is legally flawed
and ultimately does more harm than good to strengthen welfare rights"
(210-11).
22. In his dissent, Justice Stewart
finds plausible, as one "rational basis" for the kind of laws at issue in
this case, the idea that "a residence requirement provides an objective
and workable means of determining that an applicant intends to remain
indefinitely within the jurisdiction" (Shapiro 673).
23. In his dissent to
Shapiro, Justice Harlan cites his own previous dissent in
Harper v. Virginia Board of Elections 383 U.S. 663 (1966), a
well-known case that ruled that poll taxes were unconstitutional. In
that earlier case, Harlan had suggested that "it was probably accepted as
sound political theory by a large percentage of Americans through most of
our history, that people with some property have a deeper stake in
community affairs, and are consequently more responsible, more educated,
more knowledgeable, more worthy of confidence, than those without means,
and that the community and Nation would be better managed if the
franchise were restricted to such citizens" (Harper 683).
24. This provision seems, however, to
have been declared unconstitutional by the Supreme Court's 1999 decision,
Saenz v. Roe, which reaffirmed Shapiro's
assertion of the right to travel.
25. In his "Afterthought on 'The Right
to Welfare,'" for example, Marshall discusses how one British welfare
agency, the Supplementary Benefits Commission, had adapted a
"discretionary" model in the years following his original essay, but that
such a policy had been found "to cause conflict, unhappy comparisons
between the workless and the working poor and complaints from those who
did not believe that they were getting their 'rights'" (96).
26. This is not the place for a
detailed exposition of the enduring tradition of thought concerning a
guaranteed social income, or what has recently been dubbed a "universal
basic income" or "UBI" (see Parijs). But we very briefly observe how one
tradition of this thought, influenced in part by Henry George's famous
idea of a land-value tax, considers the natural environment as a kind of
common patrimony whose value should be divided among all citizens--an
idea grounded absolutely in the most mechanical kind of economic
calculation. The idea of a "negative income tax" or basic
minimum income--which has sometimes been advocated even by
right-wing thinkers such as Milton Friedman--also tends to fall prey to
questions of common being (what are basic needs?) and calculation (how
much can society afford to give?). For example, Robert Solow, in his
preface to Parijs, suggests "a very low-level UBI would be feasible in
economic, even budgetary, terms, especially because it would at least
partially replace some current means-tested transfers" (Parijs xiii).
In other words, UBI would just be "welfare" or "relief" under another name.
27. For this phrase, see Nancy's
The Gravity of Thought.
28. See, for example, Resnick and
Wolff 37.
Works Cited
Agamben, Giorgio. The Coming Community. Trans.
Michael Hardt. Minneapolis, MN: U of Minnesota P, 1993.
---. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life.
Stanford, CA: Stanford UP, 1998.
Anderson, Martin. Welfare: The Political Economy of Welfare
Reform in the United States. Palo Alto, CA: Hoover Institution P,
1978.
Bennington, Geoff. Legislations: The Politics of
Deconstruction. London: Verso, 1994.
Blanchot, Maurice. The Unavowable Community.
Trans. Pierre Joris. Barrytown, NY: Station Hill, 1988.
Brown v. Board of Education. 347 U.S. Supreme Court
483. 1954.
Bussiere, Elizabeth. (Dis)entitling the Poor: The Warren
Court, Welfare Rights, and the American Political Tradition.
University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State UP, 1997.
City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co. 488 U.S. Supreme
Court 469. 1989.
Cornell, Drucilla. Beyond Accommodation: Ethical Feminism,
Deconstruction, and the Law. 2nd ed. Lanham, MD: Rowman &
Littlefield, 1999.
Dandridge v. Williams. 397 U.S. Supreme Court 471.
1970.
Delgado, Richard. "Affirmative Action as a Majoritarian Device:
Or, Do You Really Want to Be a Role Model?" Critical Race Theory:
The Cutting Edge. Ed. Richard Delgado. Philadelphia: Temple UP,
1995. 355-61.
---. The Coming Race War? And Other
Apocalyptic Tales of America after Affirmative Action and
Welfare. New York: New York UP, 1996.
Derrida, Jacques. "Force of Law: The 'Mystical Foundation of
Authority'." Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice.
Ed. Drucilla Cornell, Michael Rosenfeld, and David Gray Carlson. New
York: Routledge, 1992. 3-67.
---. "Racism's Last Word." Trans. Peggy Kamuf. Critical
Inquiry 12 (Autumn 1985): 290-299.
---. Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of
Mourning, and the New International. Trans. Peggy Kamuf. New
York: Routledge, 1994.
Derrida, Jacques, and Maurizio Ferraris. A Taste for the
Secret. Trans. Giacomo Donis. Ed. Giacomo Donis and David
Webb. Cambridge, UK: Polity P, 2001.
Derrida, Jacques, and Mustapha Tlili, eds. For Nelson
Mandela. New York: Seaver, 1987.
Dworkin, Ronald. A Matter of Principle. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard UP, 1985.
Fiscus, Ronald J. The Constitutional Logic of Affirmative
Action: Making the Case for Quotas. Ed. Stephen L. Wasby.
Foreword Stanley Fish. Durham, NC: Duke UP, 1992.
Flagg, Barbara J. Was Blind But Now I See: White Race
Consciousness and the Law. New York and London: New York UP, 1998.
Fraser, Nancy, and Linda Gordon. "'Dependency' Demystified:
Inscriptions of Power in a Keyword of the Welfare State."
Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Anthology. Ed. Robert
E. Goodin and Philip Pettit. Oxford, UK: Blackwell, 1997. 618-633.
Fullilove v. Klutznick. 448 U.S. Supreme Court
448. 1980.
Gans, Herbert. The War Against the Poor: The Underclass and
Antipoverty Policy. New York: Basic Books, 1995.
Gilder, George. Wealth and Poverty. New York: Basic
Books, 1993.
Gordon, Linda. Pitied But Not Entitled: Single Mothers and
the History of Welfare. New York, Free P, 1994.
Gotanda, Neil. "A Critique of 'Our Constitution Is
Color-Blind'." Stanford Law Review 44.1 (November 1991):
1-68.
Gratz v. Bollinger. U.S. Dist. Court, E. Mich.,
South. Div. 2000. <http://www.mied.uscourts.gov/_opinions/Dugganpdf/PJD97cv75231.pdf>.
Griffin v. Illinois 351 U.S. Supreme Court 12. 1956.
Grutter v. Bollinger. U.S. Dist. Court, E. Mich.,
South. Div. 2001. <http://www.mied.uscourts.gov/_opinions/Friedmanpdf/BAF97cv75928.pdf>.
Guinier, Lani and Susan Sturm, eds. Who's
Qualified? Boston, MA: Beacon, 2001.
Gurin, Patricia. "Empirical Results from the Analyses Conducted
for this Litigation." <http://www.umich.edu/~urel/admissions/legal/expert/empir.html>.
---. "The Studies: Method and Measures." <http://www.umich.edu/~urel/admissions/legal/expert/studies.html>.
---. "Theoretical Foundations for the Effect of Diversity."
<http://www.umich.edu/~urel/admissions/legal/expert/theor.html>.
Gutmann, Amy. "Introduction." Solow vii-xv.
Handler, Joel F. The Poverty of Welfare Reform. New
Haven, CT: Yale UP, 1995.
Handler, Joel F., and Yeheskel Hansenfeld. The Moral
Construction of Poverty: Welfare Reform in America. Newbury Park,
CA: Sage, 1991.
Hardt, Michael, and Antonio Negri. Empire. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard UP, 2000.
Harper v. Virginia Board of Elections. 383 U.S.
Supreme Court 663. 1966.
Harris, Cheryl I. "Whiteness as Property." Harvard Law
Review 106 (1993): 1709-91.
Harris, Nigel. The New Untouchables: Immigration and the
New World Order. London: I. B. Tauris, 1995.
Himmelfarb, Gertrude. The De-Moralization of Society: From
Victorian Virtues to Modern Values. New York: Knopf, 1995.
Hirabayashi v. United States. 320 U.S. Supreme Court
81. 1942.
Hopwood v. Texas. 78 F.3d. 5th U.S. Circuit 932. 1996.
Katz, Michael B. In the Shadow of the Poorhouse: A Social
History of Welfare in America. Revised ed. New York: Basic
Books, 1996.
---. The Undeserving Poor: From the War on Poverty to the
War on Welfare. Revised ed. New York: Pantheon, 1989.
Klinkner, Philip A., with Rogers M. Smith. The Unsteady
March: The Rise and Decline of Racial Equality in America.
Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1999.
Korematsu v. United States. 323 U.S. Supreme Court
214. 1944.
Kozol, Jonathan. Savage Inequalities: Children in America's
Schools. New York: Crown, 1991.
Kull, Andrew. The Color-Blind Constitution.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1992.
Kurland, Philip B., and Gerhard Casper, eds. Landmark
Briefs and Arguments of the Supreme Court of the United States:
Constitutional Law. Arlington, VA: U Publications of
America, 1975.
Levinas, Emmanuel. "The Trace of the Other." Trans. Alphonso
Lingis. Deconstruction in Context: Literature and
Philosophy. Ed. Mark C. Taylor. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1986.
Marable, Manning. How Capitalism Underdeveloped Black
America: Problems in Race, Political Economy, and Society.
Updated ed. Boston, MA: South End, 2000.
Marshall, T. H. The Right to Welfare and Other
Essays. New York: Free P, 1981.
Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. The Marx-Engels
Reader. 2nd ed. Ed. Robert Tucker. New York: Norton,
1978.
Mead, Lawrence M. Beyond Entitlement: The Social
Obligations of Citizenship. New York: Free P, 1986.
Mehuron, Tamar Ann, ed. Points of Light: New Approaches to
Ending Welfare Dependency. Washington, DC: Ethics and Public
Policy Center, 1990.
Michaelsen, Scott. The Limits of Multiculturalism:
Interrogating the Origins of American Anthropology. Minneapolis, MN:
Minnesota UP, 1999.
Mills, Charles W. The Racial Contract. Ithaca, NY:
Cornell UP, 1997.
Mouffe, Chantal. The Democratic Paradox. New York:
Verso, 2000.
Murray, Charles. Losing Ground: American Social Policy,
1950-1980. New York: Basic Books, 1984.
---. "Preface." The Tragedy of American
Compassion. Washington, D.C.: Regnery Publishing, 1992.
Nancy, Jean-Luc. The Gravity of Thought. Trans.
François Raffoul and Gregory Recco. Atlantic Highlands, NJ:
Humanities P, 1997.
---. The Inoperative Community. Trans. Peter
Connor, et. al. Minneapolis, MN: U of Minnesota P, 1991.
Nixon, Bryce. "'Rational Basis with a Bite': A Retreat from the
Constitutional Right to Travel." Law & Inequality Journal
18 (Winter 2000): 209-242.
Oh, Reggie, and Frank Wu. "The Evolution of Race in the Law: The
Supreme Court Moves from Approving Internment of Japanese Americans to
Disapproving Affirmative Action for African Americans." Journal of
Race and Law (Winter 1996): 165-93.
Olasky, Marvin. The Tragedy of American Compassion.
Washington, D.C.: Regnery Publishing, 1992.
Olasky, Marvin, and George W. Bush. Compassionate
Conservatism: What It Is, What It Does, and How It Can Transform
America. New York: Free P, 2000.
Parijs, Philippe Van. What's Wrong With a Free
Lunch? Ed. Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers. Forward by Robert M.
Solow. Boston, MA: Beacon P, 2001.
Piven, Frances Fox, and Richard A. Cloward. Regulating the
Poor: The Functions of Public Welfare. New York: Pantheon
Books, 1971.
Post, Robert. "Introduction: After Bakke." Post
and Rogin 13-27.
Post, Robert, and Michael Rogin, eds. Race and
Representation: Affirmative Action. New York: Zone, 1998.
Regents of U of California v. Bakke. 438 U.S. Supreme
Court 265. 1978.
Resnick, Stephen A., and Richard D. Wolff. Knowledge and
Class: A Marxian Critique of Political Economy. Chicago and
London: U of Chicago P, 1987.
Schmitt, Carl. Political Theology: Four Chapters on the
Concept of Sovereignty. 1922. Trans. George Schwab. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, 1985.
Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.S. Supreme Court 618.
1969.
Shershow, Scott Cutler. "Of Sinking: Marxism and the 'General'
Economy." Critical Inquiry 27 (Spring 2001): 468-92.
Sidel, Ruth. Keeping Women and Children Last: America's War
on the Poor. New York: Penguin, 1996.
Shklar, Judith N. American Citizenship: The Quest for
Inclusion. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1991.
Siegal, Reva B. "The Racial Rhetorics of Colorblind
Constitutionalism: The Case of Hopwood v. Texas." Post and
Rogin 29-72.
Solow, Robert M. Work and Welfare. Ed. Amy Gutmann.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP, 1998.
Spann, Girardeau A. The Law of Affirmative Action:
Twenty-Five Years of Supreme Court Decisions on Race and
Remedies. New York and London: New York UP, 2000.
---. Race Against the Court: The Supreme Court & Minorities
in Contemporary America. New York and London: New York UP, 1993.
Sparer, Edward V. "The Right to Welfare." The Rights of
Americans: What They Are--What They Should Be. Ed. Norman
Dorsen. New York: Pantheon, 1970. 65-93.
Sprinker, Michael, ed. Ghostly Demarcations: A Symposium on
Jacques Derrida's Spectres of Marx. New York: Verso, 1999.
Sunstein, Cass R. One Case at a Time: Judicial Minimalism
on the Supreme Court. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1999.
Trattner, Walter I. From Poor Law to Welfare State: A
History of Social Welfare in America. 5th ed. New York: Free P,
1994.
Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. Democracy Realized: The
Progressive Alternative. London: Verso, 1998.
United States. Cong. House. Committee on the Budget. Welfare and Medicaid
Reform Act of 1996. HR 3734. Washington: GPO, 1996.
Walzer, Michael. Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism
and Equality. New York: Basic Books, 1983.
Weaver, R. Kent. Ending Welfare as We Know It.
Washington, DC: Brookings Institution P, 2000.
Wilson, William Julius. When Work Disappears: The World of
the New Urban Poor. New York: Random House, 1996.
Wygant v. Jackson Board of Education. 476 U.S.
Supreme Court 267. 1986.
|