- Max Stirner and Michel Foucault are two thinkers not often examined
together. However, it has been suggested that the long-ignored Stirner may be seen as a precursor to contemporary
poststructuralist thought.[1] Indeed, there are many extraordinary
parallels between Stirner's critique of Enlightenment humanism, universal
rationality, and essential identities, and similar critiques developed by
thinkers such as Foucault, Jacques Derrida, Gilles Deleuze, and others.
However, the purpose of this paper is not merely to situate Stirner in the
"poststructuralist" tradition, but rather to examine his thinking on the
question of freedom, and to explore the connections here with Foucault's
own development of the concept in the context of power relations and
subjectivity. Broadly speaking, both thinkers see the classical Kantian
idea of freedom as deeply problematic, as it involves essentialist and
universal presuppositions which are themselves often oppressive. Rather,
the concept of freedom must be rethought. It can no longer be seen in
solely negative terms, as freedom from constraint, but must involve more
positive notions of individual autonomy, particularly the freedom of the
individual to construct new modes of subjectivity. Stirner, as we shall
see, dispenses with the classical notion of freedom altogether and
develops a theory of ownness [Eigneheit] to describe this radical individual
autonomy. I suggest in this paper that such a theory of ownness as a
non-essentialist form of freedom has many similarities with Foucault's
own project of freedom, which involves a critical ethos and an
aestheticization of the self. Indeed, Foucault questions the
anthropological and universal rational foundations of the discourse of
freedom, redefining it in terms of ethical practices.[2] Both Stirner and Foucault are therefore crucial to
the understanding of freedom in a contemporary sense--they show that
freedom can no longer be limited by rational absolutes and universal
moral categories. They take the understanding of freedom beyond the
confines of the Kantian project--grounding it instead in concrete and
contingent strategies of the self.
Kant and Universal Freedom
- In order to understand how this radical reformulation of freedom
can take place, we must first see how the concept of freedom is located
in Enlightenment thought. In this paradigm, the exercise of freedom is
seen as an inherently rational property. According to Immanuel Kant, for
instance, human freedom is presupposed by moral law that is rationally
understood. In the Critique of Practical Reason, Kant seeks
to establish an absolute rational ground for moral thinking beyond
empirical principles. He argues that empirical principles are not an
appropriate basis for moral laws because they do not allow their true
universality to be established. Rather, morality should be based on a
universal law--a categorical imperative--which can be rationally
understood. For Kant, then, there is only one categorical imperative,
which provides a foundation for all rational human action: "Act only
on that maxim whereby thou canst at the same time will that it should
become a universal law" (38). In other words, the morality of an
action is determined by whether or not it should become a universal law,
applicable to all situations. Kant outlines three features of all moral
maxims. Firstly, they must have the form of universality. Secondly, they
must have a rational end. Thirdly, the maxims that arise from the
autonomous legislation of the individual should be in accordance with a
certain teleology of ends.
- This last point has important consequences for the question of
human freedom. For Kant, moral law is based on freedom--the rational
individual freely chooses out of a sense of duty to adhere to universal
moral maxims. Thus, for moral laws to be rationally grounded they cannot
be based on any form of coercion or constraint. They must be freely
adhered to as a rational act of the individual. Freedom is seen by Kant
as an autonomy of the will--the freedom of the rational individual to
follow the dictates of his own reason by adhering to these universal
moral laws. This autonomy of the will, then, is for Kant the supreme
principle of morality. He defines it as "that property of it by which it
is a law to itself (independently of any property of objects of volition)"
(59). Freedom is, therefore, the ability of the individual to legislate
for him or herself, free from external forces. However, this freedom of
self-legislation must be in accordance with universal moral categories.
Hence, for Kant, the principle of autonomy is: "Never choose except in
such a way that the maxims of the choice are comprehended in the same
volition as a universal law" (59). It would appear that there is a
central paradox in this idea of freedom--you are free to choose as
long as you make the right choice, as long as you choose universal moral
maxims. However, for Kant there is no contradiction here because,
although adherence to moral laws is a duty and an absolute imperative, it
is still a duty that is freely chosen by the individual. Moral laws are
rationally established, and because freedom can only be exercised by
rational individuals, they will necessarily, yet freely, choose to obey
these moral laws. In other words, an action is free only insofar as it
conforms to moral and rational imperatives--otherwise it is pathological
and therefore "unfree." In this way, freedom and the categorical
imperative are not antagonistic but, rather, mutually dependent concepts.
Individual autonomy, for Kant, is the very basis of moral laws.
But that the principle of autonomy [...] is the sole principle of morals can
be readily shown by mere analysis of concepts of morality; for by
this analysis we find that its principle must be a categorical imperative,
and that [the imperative] commands neither more nor less than this very
autonomy. (59)
The Authoritarian Obverse
- Nevertheless, it would seem that there is a hidden
authoritarianism in Kant's formulation of freedom. While the individual
is free to act in accordance with the dictates of his own reason, he must
nevertheless obey universal moral maxims. Kant's moral philosophy is a
philosophy of the law. That is why Jacques Lacan was able to diagnose a
hidden jouissance--or enjoyment in excess of the law--that
attached itself to Kant's categorical imperative. According to Lacan,
Sade is the necessary counterpart to Kant--the perverse pleasure that
attaches itself to the law becomes, in the Sadeian universe, the law of
pleasure.[3] The thing that binds
Kantian freedom to the law is its attachment to an absolute rationality.
It is precisely because freedom must be exercised rationally that the
individual finds him or herself dutifully obeying rationally founded
universal moral laws.
- However, both Foucault and Stirner have called into question such
universal rational and moral categories, which are central to
Enlightenment thought. They contend that absolute categories of morality
and rationality sanction various forms of domination and exclusion and
deny individual difference. For Foucault, for instance, the centrality of
reason in our society is based on the radical and violent exclusion of
madness. People are still excluded, incarcerated, and oppressed because of
this arbitrary division between reason and unreason, rationality and
irrationality. Similarly, the prison system is based on a division
between good and evil, innocence and guilt. The incarceration of the
prisoner is made possible only through the universalization of
moral codes. What must be challenged, for Foucault, are not only the
practices of domination that are found in the prison, but also the
morality which justifies and rationalizes these practices. The main focus
of Foucault's critique of the prison is not necessarily on the domination
within, but on the fact that this domination is justified on absolute
moral grounds--the moral grounds that Kant seeks to make universal.
Foucault wants to disrupt the "serene domination of Good over Evil"
central to moral discourses and practices of power ("Intellectuals" 204-17).
- It is this moral absolutism that Stirner is also opposed to. He
sees morality as a "spook"--an abstract ideal that has been placed beyond
the individual and held over him in an oppressive and alienating way.
Morality and rationality have become "fixed ideas"--ideas that have come
to be seen as sacred and absolute. A fixed idea, according to Stirner, is
an abstract concept that governs thought--a discursively closed fiction
that denies difference and plurality. They are ideas that have been
abstracted from the world and continue to dominate the individual by
comparing him or her to an ideal norm that is impossible to attain. In
other words, Kant's project of taking moral maxims out of the empirical
world and into a transcendental realm where they would apply universally,
would be seen by Stirner as a project of alienation and domination.
Kant's invocation of absolute obedience to universal moral maxims Stirner
would see as the worst possible denial of individuality. For Stirner, the
individual is paramount, and anything which purports to apply to or speak
for everyone universally is an effacement of individual uniqueness and
difference. The individual is plagued by these abstract ideals, these
apparitions that are not of his own creation and are imposed on him,
confronting him with impossible moral and rational standards. As we shall
see, moreover, the individual for Stirner is not a stable, fixed identity
or essence--this would be just as much an idealist abstraction as the
specters that oppress it. Rather, individuality may be seen here in terms
similar to Foucault's--as a radically contingent form of subjectivity, an
open strategy that one engages in to question and contest the confines of
essentialism.
The Critique of Essentialism
- The exorcism that Stirner performs on this "spirit realm" of moral
and rational absolutes is part of a radical critique of Enlightenment
humanism and idealism. His "epistemological break" with humanism may be
seen most clearly in his repudiation of Ludwig Feuerbach. In The Essence
of Christianity, Feuerbach applied the notion of alienation to religion.
Religion is alienating, according to Feuerbach, because it requires that
man abdicate his essential qualities and powers by projecting them onto
an abstract God beyond the grasp of humanity. For Feuerbach, the
predicates of God were really only the predicates of man as a species
being. God was an illusion, a fictitious projection of the essential
qualities of man. In other words, God was a reification of human essence.
Like Kant, who tried to transcend the dogmatism of metaphysics by
reconstructing it on rational and scientific grounds, Feuerbach wanted to
overcome religious alienation by re-establishing the universal rational
and moral capacities of man as the fundamental ground for human
experience. Feuerbach embodies the Enlightenment humanist project of
restoring man to his rightful place at the center of the universe, of
making the human the divine, the finite the infinite.
- Stirner argues, however, that by seeking the sacred in "human
essence," by positing an essential and universal subject and attributing
to him certain qualities that had hitherto been attributed to God,
Feuerbach has merely reintroduced religious alienation, placing the
abstract concept of man within the category of the Divine. Through the
Feuerbachian inversion man becomes like God, and just as man was debased
under God, so the individual is debased beneath this perfect being, man.
For Stirner, man is just as oppressive, if not more so, than God. Man
becomes the substitute for the Christian illusion. Feuerbach, Stirner
argues, is the high priest of a new universal religion--humanism: "The
human religion is only the last metamorphosis of the Christian
religion" (158). It is important to note here that Stirner's concept of
alienation is fundamentally different from the Feuerbachian humanist
understanding as alienation from one's essence. Stirner radicalizes the
theory of alienation by seeing this essence as itself alienating. As I
shall suggest, alienation in this instance may be seen more along the
lines of a Foucauldian notion of domination--as a discourse that ties the
individual to a certain subjectivity through the conviction that there
lies within everyone an essence to be revealed.
- According to Stirner, it is this notion of a universal human
essence that provides the foundations for the absolutization of moral and
rational ideas. These maxims have become sacred and immutable because
they are now based on the notion of humanity, on man's essence, and to
transgress them would be a transgression of this very essence. In this
way the subject is brought into conflict with itself. Man is, in a sense,
haunted and alienated by himself, by the specter of "essence" inside him:
"Henceforth man no longer, in typical cases, shudders at ghosts outside
him, but at himself; he is terrified at himself" (Stirner 41). So for
Stirner, Feuerbach's "insurrection" has not overthrown the category of
religious authority--it has merely installed man within it, reversing the
order of subject and predicate. In the same way, we might suggest that
Kant's metaphysical "insurrection" has not overthrown dogmatic structures
of belief, but only installed morality and rationality within them.
- While Kant wanted to take morality out of the domain of religion,
founding it instead on reason, Stirner maintains that morality is only
the old religious dogmatism in a new, rational guise: "Moral faith is as
fanatical as religious faith!" (45). What Stirner objects to is not
morality itself, but the fact that it has become a sacred, unbreakable
law, and he exposes the will to power, the cruelty and the domination
behind moral ideas. Morality is based on the desecration, the breaking
down of the individual will. The individual must conform to prevailing
moral codes; otherwise, he becomes alienated from his essence. For Stirner,
moral coercion is just as vicious as the coercion carried out by the
state, only it is more insidious and subtle, since it does not require the use
of physical force. The warden of morality is already installed in the
individual's conscience. This internalized moral surveillance is also
found in Foucault's discussion of Panopticism--in which he argues,
reversing the classical paradigm, that the soul becomes the prison for the
body (Foucault, Discipline 195-228).
- A similar critique may be leveled at rationality. Rational truths
are always held above individual perspectives, and Stirner argues that
this is merely another way of dominating the individual. As with
morality, Stirner is not necessarily against rational truth itself, but
rather against the way it has become sacred, transcendental, and removed from the
grasp of the individual, thus abrogating the individual's power. Stirner
says: "As long as you believe in the truth, you do not believe in
yourself, and you are a --servant, a--religious man" (312). Rational
truth, for Stirner, has no real meaning beyond individual
perspectives--it is something that can be used by the individual. Its
real basis, as with morality, is power.
- So while, for Kant, moral maxims are rationally and freely obeyed,
for Stirner they are a coercive standard, based on an alienating notion
of human "essence" that is forced upon the individual. Moreover, they
become the basis for practices of punishment and domination. For
instance, in response to the Enlightenment idea that crime was a disease
to be cured rather than a moral failing to be punished, Stirner argues
that curative and punitive strategies were just two sides of the same old
moral prejudice. Both strategies rely on a universal norm which must be
adhered to: "'curative means' always announces to begin with that
individuals will be looked on as 'called' to a particular 'salvation' and
hence treated according to the requirements of this 'human calling'"
(213). Is not the individual, for Kant, also "called" to a particular
"salvation" when he is required to do his duty and obey moral codes? Is
not the Kantian categorical imperative also a "human calling" in this
sense? In other words, Stirner's critique of morality and rationality may
be applied to Kant's categorical imperative. For Stirner, although moral
maxims may be ostensibly freely followed, they still entail a hidden
coercion and authoritarianism. This is because they have become
universalized in the Kantian formulation as absolute norms which leave
little room for individual autonomy, and which one cannot transgress,
because to do so would be to go against one's own rational, universal
"human calling."
- Stirner's critique of morality and its relation to punishment has
striking similarities with Foucault's own writings on punishment. For
Stirner, as we have seen, there is no difference between cure and
punishment--the practice of curing is a reapplication of the old moral prejudices in a new
"enlightened" guise:
Curative means or healing is only the reverse side of
punishment, the theory of cure runs parallel with the
theory of punishment; if the latter sees in an action a sin against right,
the former takes it for a sin of the man against himself, as a
falling away from his health. (213)
- This is very similar to Foucault's argument about the modern
formula of punishment--that medical and psychiatric norms are only the old
morality in a new guise. While Stirner considers the effect of such forms
of moral hygiene on the individual conscience, where Foucault's focus is
more on the materiality of the body, the formula of cure and punishment
is the same: it is the notion of what is properly "human" that authorizes
a whole series of exclusions, disciplinary practices, and restrictive
moral and rational norms. For Foucault, as well as for Stirner,
punishment is made possible by making something sacred or absolute--in
the way that Kant makes morality into a universal law. There are several
points to be made here. Firstly, both Stirner and Foucault see moral and
rational discourses as problematic--they often exclude, marginalize, and
oppress those who do not live up to the norms implicit in these
discourses. Secondly, both thinkers see rationality and morality as being
implicated in power relations, rather than constituting a critical
epistemological point outside power. Not only are these norms made
possible by practices of power, through the exclusion and domination of
the other, but they also, in turn, justify and perpetuate practices of power,
such as those found in the prison and asylum.
- Thirdly, both thinkers see morality as having an ambiguous
relation to freedom. While Stirner argues that on the surface moral and
rational norms are freely adhered to, they nevertheless entail an
oppression over ourselves--a self-domination--that is far more insidious
and effective than straightforward coercion. In other words, by
conforming to universally prevailing moral and rational norms, the
individual abdicates his own power and allows himself to be dominated.
Foucault also unmasks this hidden domination of the moral and rational
norm that is found behind the calm visage of human freedom. The classical
Enlightenment idea of freedom, Foucault argues, allowed only
pseudo-sovereignty. It claims to hold sovereign "consciousness
(sovereign in the context of judgment, but subjected to the necessities
of truth), the individual (a titular control of personal rights subjected
to the laws of nature and society), basic freedom (sovereign within, but
accepting the demands of an outside world and 'aligned with destiny')"
(Foucault, "Revolutionary" 221). In other words, Enlightenment
humanism claims to free individuals from all sorts of institutional
oppressions while, at the same time, entailing an intensification of
oppression over the self and denial of the power to resist this
subjection. This subordination at the heart of freedom may be seen in the
Kantian categorical imperative: while it is based on a freedom of
consciousness, this freedom is nevertheless subject to absolute
rational and moral categories. Classical freedom only liberates a certain
form of subjectivity, while intensifying domination over the individual
who is subordinated by these moral and rational criteria. That is to say
that the discourse of freedom is based on a specific form of
subjectivity--the autonomous, rational man of the Enlightenment and
liberalism. As Foucault and Stirner show, this form of freedom is only
made possible through the domination and exclusion of other modes of
subjectivity that do not conform to this rational model. In other
words, while morality does not deny or constrain freedom in an overt
way--in Kant's case moral maxims are based on the individual's freedom of
choice--this freedom is nevertheless restricted in a more subtle fashion
because it is required to conform to moral and rational absolutes.
- It is clear, then, that for both Stirner and Foucault, the
classical Kantian idea of freedom is deeply problematic. It constructs
the individual as "rational" and "free" while subjecting him to absolute
moral and rational norms, and dividing him into rational and irrational,
moral and immoral selves. The individual freely conforms to these
rational norms, and in this way his subjectivity is constructed as a site
of its own oppression. The silent tyranny of the self-imposed norm has
become the prevailing mode of subjection. While for Kant, moral maxims
and rational norms existed in a complementary relationship with freedom,
for Stirner and Foucault the relationship is much more paradoxical and
conflicting. It is not that transcendental moral and rational norms deny
freedom per se--indeed in the Kantian paradigm they presuppose freedom.
It is rather that the form of freedom brought into being through these
absolute categories implies other, more subtle forms of domination. This
domination is made possible precisely because freedom's relationship with
power is masked. For Kant, as we have seen, freedom is an absence from
coercion. However, for Stirner and Foucault, freedom is always implicated
in power relations--power relations that are creative as well as
restrictive. To ignore this, moreover, to perpetuate the comforting
illusion that freedom promises a universal liberation from power, is to
play right into the hands of domination. It may be argued, then, that
Foucault and Stirner uncover, in different ways, the authoritarian
underside or the "other scene" of Kantian freedom.
Foucauldian Freedom: The Care of the Self
- This does not mean, however, that Stirner and Foucault reject the
idea of freedom. On the contrary, they interrogate the limits of the
Enlightenment project of freedom in order to expand it--to invent new
forms of freedom and autonomy that go beyond the restrictions of
the categorical imperative. Indeed, as Olivia Custer shows, Foucault is as engaged as Kant in the problematic of freedom.
However, as we shall see, he seeks to approach the question of freedom in a different
way--through concrete ethical strategies and practices of the self.
- For Foucault, the illusion of a state of freedom beyond the world
of power must be dispelled. Moreover, freedom's attachment to
essentialist categories and pre-ordained moral and rational coordinates
must at least be questioned. However, the concept of freedom is very
important for Foucault--he does not want to dispense with it, but rather
to situate it in a realm of power relations that necessarily make it
indeterminate. It is only through a rethinking of freedom in this way
that it can be wrested from the metaphysical world and brought to the
level of the individual. Rather than the abstract Kantian notion of
freedom as a rational choice beyond constraints and limitations, freedom
for Foucault exists in mutual and reciprocal relations with power.
Moreover, rather than freedom being presupposed by absolute moral maxims,
it is actually presupposed by power. According to Foucault, power may be
understood as a series of "actions upon the action of others" in which
multiple discourses, counterdiscourses, strategies, and technologies
clash with one another--specific relations of power always provoking
specific and localized relations of resistance. Resistance is something
that exceeds power and is at the same time integral to its dynamic. Power
is based on a certain freedom of action, a certain choice of
possibilities. In this sense, "power is exercised only over free
subjects, and only insofar as they are free" (Foucault, "Subject"
208-26). Unlike classical schema in which power and freedom were diagrammatically opposed, Foucauldian thinking asserts the
total dependency of the former on the latter. Where there is no freedom, where the field of action is
absolutely restricted and determined, according to Foucault, there
can be no power: slavery, for instance, is not a power relationship
(Foucault, "Subject" 221).
- Foucault's notion of freedom is a radical departure from Kant's.
Whereas, for Kant, freedom is abstracted from the constraints and
limitations of power, for Foucault, freedom is the very basis of
these limits and constraints. Freedom is not a metaphysical and
transcendental concept. Rather, it is entirely of this world and exists
in a complicated and entangled relationship with power. Indeed, there can
be no possibility of a world free from power relations, as power and
freedom cannot exist without one another.
- Moreover, Foucault is able to see freedom as being implicated in
power relations because, for him, freedom is more than just the absence or negation of constraint. He rejects the "repressive"
model of freedom which presupposes an essential self--a universal human nature--that is
restricted and needs to be liberated. The liberation of an essential
subjectivity is the basis of classical Enlightenment notions of freedom
and is still central to our political imaginary. However, both Foucault
and Stirner reject this idea of an essential self--this is merely an
illusion created by power. As Foucault says, "The man described for us,
whom we are invited to free, is already in himself the effect of a
subjection much more profound than himself" (Discipline 30).
While he does not discount acts of political liberation--for example when
a people tries to liberate itself from colonial rule--this cannot operate
as the basis for an ongoing mode of freedom. To suppose that freedom can
be established eternally on the basis of this initial act of liberation
is only to invite new forms of domination. If freedom is to be an
enduring feature of any political society it must be seen as a
practice--an ongoing strategy and mode of action that
continuously challenges and questions relations of power.
- This practice of freedom is also a creative practice--a continuous
process of self-formation of the subject. It is in this sense that
freedom may be seen as positive. One of the features that characterizes
modernity, according to Foucault, is a Baudelairean "heroic" attitude
toward the present. For Baudelaire, the contingent, fleeting nature of
modernity is to be confronted with a certain "attitude" toward the
present that is concomitant with a new mode of relationship that one has
with oneself. This involves a reinvention of the self: "This modernity
does not 'liberate man in his own being'; it compels him to face the task
of producing himself" (Foucault, "What" 42). So, rather than freedom
being a liberation of man's essential self from external constraints, it
is an active and deliberate practice of inventing oneself. This practice
of freedom may be found in the example of the dandy, or
flâneur, "who makes of his body, his behavior, his feelings
and passions, his very existence, a work of art" (Foucault, "What" 41-2).
It is this practice of self-aestheticization that allows us,
according to Foucault, to reflect critically on the limits of our time.
It does not seek a metaphysical place beyond all limits, but rather works
within the limits and constraints of the present. More importantly,
however, it is also a work conducted upon the limits of ourselves and our
own identities. Because power operates through a process of
subjectification--by tying the individual to an essential
identity--the radical reconstitution of the self is a necessary act of
resistance. This idea of freedom, then, defines a new form of politics
more relevant to contemporary regimes of power: "The political, ethical,
social, philosophical problem of our days is not to liberate the
individual from the State and its institutions, but to liberate ourselves
from the State and the type of individualisation linked to it" (Foucault,
"Subject" 216).
- For Foucault, moreover, the liberation of the self is a
distinctly ethical practice. It involves a notion of "care for
the self" whereby one's desires and behavior are regulated by oneself so
that freedom may be practiced ethically. This sensitivity to the care for
oneself and the ethical practice of freedom could be found, Foucault
suggests, among the Greeks and Romans of antiquity. For them the freedom
of the individual was an ethical problem. Because the desire for power
over others was also a threat to one's own freedom, the exercise of power
was something that had to be regulated, monitored, and limited. To be a
slave to one's own desires was as bad as being subject to another's
desires. This regulation of one's desires and practices required an
ethics of behavior that one constructed for oneself. In order to practice
freedom ethically, in order to be truly free, one had to achieve power
over oneself, over one's desires. As Foucault shows, in ancient Greek and
Roman thinking, "the good ruler is precisely the one who exercises his
power correctly, i.e., by exercising at the same time his power on
himself" ("Ethics" 288).
- This ethical practice of freedom associated with the care for the
self begins, however, at a certain point to sound somewhat Kantian. Indeed, as Foucault says,
"for what is ethics, if not the practice of freedom? [...]. Freedom is
the ontological condition of ethics" ("Ethics" 284). Does this not appear to
re-invoke the categorical imperative where, for Kant, morality
presupposes and is founded on freedom? Has Foucault, in his attempt to
escape the absolutism of morality and rationality, reintroduced the
categorical imperative in this careful regulation of behavior and desire?
There can be no doubt about the stringency of this form of ethics. In The Use of Pleasure and The Care of the Self,
Foucault describes the Greeks' and Romans' prescriptions concerning everything
from diet and exercise to sex. However, I would suggest that there is an
important difference between the ethics of care and the universal moral
maxims insisted on by Kant. The regulation of behavior and the
problematization of freedom central to the ethic of care are things
that one applies to oneself, rather than being imposed externally from a
universal point beyond the individual. Foucault's practice of freedom is,
in this sense, an ethics, rather than a morality. It is a
certain consistency of modes and behaviors that has as its object the
consideration and problematization of the self. In other words, it allows
the self to be seen as an open project to be constituted through the
ethical practices of the individual, rather than as something defined
a priori by universal, transcendental laws. Moral laws do not
apply here--there is no transcendental authority or universal imperative
that sanctions these ethical practices and penalizes infractions.
According to Foucault, morality is defined by the type of
subjectification it entails. On the one hand, there is the morality that
enforces the code, through injunctions, and which entails a form of
subjectivity that refers the individual's conduct to these laws,
submitting it to their universal authority. This, it could be argued, is
the morality of Kant's categorical imperative. On the other hand, argues
Foucault, there is the morality in which
the accent was placed on the relationship of the self that enabled the
person to keep from being carried away by the appetites and pleasures, to
maintain a mastery and superiority over them, to keep his senses in a
state of tranquility, to remain free from interior bondage to the
passions, and to achieve a mode of being that could be defined by the
full enjoyment of oneself, or the perfect supremacy of oneself over
oneself. (Use 29-30)
- We can see, then, that Foucault's notion of freedom as an ethical
practice is radically different from Kant's idea of freedom as the basis
of universal moral law. For Foucault, freedom is ethical because it
implies an open-ended project that is conducted upon oneself, the aim of
which is to increase the power that one exercises over oneself and to limit
and regulate the power one exercises over others. In this way, one's
personal freedom and autonomy are enhanced. For Kant, on the other hand,
freedom is the basis of a metaphysical morality that must be universally
obeyed. For Foucault, in other words, ethics intensifies freedom and
autonomy, whereas for Kant, freedom and autonomy are ultimately
circumscribed by the very morality they make possible.
- So, there are two related aspects of Foucault's concept of freedom
that must be emphasized here. Firstly, there is the practice of freedom
that allows one to liberate oneself, not from external limits
that repress one's essence, but rather from the limits imposed by this
very essence. It involves, in a sense, the transgression of these limits
through a transgression and reinvention of oneself. It is a form of
freedom which operates within the limits of power, enabling the
individual to make use of the limits in inventing him/herself. Secondly,
there is the aspect of freedom that is distinctly ethical--it is a
practice of care for the self that has as its aim an increase of the
power over oneself and one's desires, thus keeping in check one's
exercise of power over others. In this way, the practice of care for the
self allows the individual to navigate an ethical course of action amidst
power relations, with the aim of intensifying freedom and personal
autonomy. Therefore, freedom is conceived as an ongoing and contingent
practice of the self that is not determined in advance by fixed moral
and rational laws.
The Two Enlightenments
- In his later essay "What Is Enlightenment?," Foucault considers
Kant's insistence on the free and public use of autonomous reason as an
escape, a "way out" for man from a state of immaturity and
subordination. While Foucault believes that this autonomous reason is
useful because it allows a critical ethos toward modernity, he refuses
the "blackmail" of the Enlightenment--the insistence that this critical
ethos at the heart of the Enlightenment be inscribed in a universal
rationality and morality. The problem with Kant is that he opens up a
space for individual autonomy and critical reflection on the limits of
oneself, only to close this space down by re-inscribing it in
transcendental notions of rationality and morality that require absolute
obedience. For Foucault, the legacy of the Enlightenment is deeply
ambiguous. As Colin Gordon shows, for Foucault there are two
Enlightenments--the Enlightenment of rational certainty, absolute
identity, and destiny, and the Enlightenment of continual questioning and
uncertainty. According to Foucault, this ambiguity is reflected in Kant's
own treatment of the Enlightenment.
- There is perhaps a Kantian moment in Foucault (or could
we say a Foucauldian moment in Kant?). Foucault shows how one
might read Kant in a heterogeneous way, focusing on the more libratory
aspect of his thinking--where we are encouraged to interrogate the limits
of modernity, to reflect critically on the way we have been constituted
as subjects. As Foucault shows, Kant sees the Enlightenment
(Aufklärung) as a critical condition, characterized by an
"audacity to know" and the free and autonomous public use of reason. This
critical condition is concomitant with a "will to revolution"--with the
attempt to understand revolution (in Kant's case the French Revolution)
as an Event that allows an interrogation of the conditions of
modernity--"an ontology of the present"--and the way we as
subjects stand in relation to it (Foucault, "Kant" 88-96). Foucault
suggests that we may adopt this critical strategy to reflect upon the
limits of the discourse of the Enlightenment itself and its universal
rational and moral injunctions. We may in this sense use the critical
capacities of the Enlightenment against itself, thus opening up spaces
for individual autonomy within its edifice, beyond the grasp of universal
laws.
- This critical stance toward the present, and the practice of the
"care for the self" with which it is bound up, outline a genealogical
strategy of freedom--a strategy that, as Foucault says "is not seeking to
make possible a metaphysics that has finally become a science; it is
seeking to give new impetus [...] to the undefined work of freedom"
("What" 46).
Stirner's Theory of Ownness
- As we shall see, it is precisely this desire to give new impetus
to freedom, to take it out of the realm of empty dreams and promises, that
is reflected in Stirner's theory of ownness. He adopts a "genealogical" approach similar to Foucault's in making the focus of
freedom the self and situating freedom amidst relations of power.
- The idea of transgressing and reinventing the self--of freeing the
self from fixed and essential identities--is also a central theme in
Stirner's thinking. As we have seen, Stirner shows that the notion of
human essence is an oppressive fiction derived from an inverted Christian
idealism that tyrannizes the individual and is linked with various
forms of political domination. Stirner describes a process of
subjectification which is very similar to Foucault's: rather than power operating as downward repression, it rules through the
subjectification of the individual, by defining him according to an
essential identity. As Stirner says: "the State betrays its enmity to me
by demanding that I be a man . . . it imposes being a man upon me as a
duty" (161). Human essence imposes a series of fixed moral and
rational ideas on the individual, which are not of his creation and which
curtail his autonomy. It is precisely this notion of duty, of moral
obligation--the same sense of duty that is the basis of the categorical
imperative--that Stirner finds oppressive.
- For Stirner, then, the individual must free him- or herself from these
oppressive ideas and obligations by first freeing himself from
essence--from the essential identity that is imposed on him. Freedom
involves, then, a transgression of essence, a transgression of the self.
But what form should this transgression take? Like Foucault, Stirner is
suspicious of the language of liberation and revolution--it is based
on a notion of an essential self that supposedly throws off the chains of
external repression. For Stirner, it is precisely this notion of
human essence that is itself oppressive. Therefore, different strategies
of freedom are called for--ones that abandon the humanist project of
liberation and seek, rather, to reconfigure the subject in new and
non-essentialist ways. To this end, Stirner calls for an
insurrection:
Revolution and insurrection must not be looked upon as synonymous. The
former consists in an overturning of conditions, of the established
condition or status, the state or society, and is accordingly a
political or social act; the latter has indeed for its
unavoidable consequence a transformation of circumstances, yet does not
start from it but from men's discontent with themselves, is not an armed
rising but a rising of individuals, a getting up without regard to the
arrangements that spring from it. The revolution aimed at new
arrangements; insurrection leads us no longer to let ourselves
be arranged, but to arrange ourselves, and sets no glittering hopes on
"institutions." It is not a fight against the established, since, if it
prospers, the established collapses of itself; it is only a working forth
of me out of the established. (279-80)
- So while a revolution aims at transforming existing social and
political conditions so that human essence may flourish, an insurrection
aims at freeing the individual from this very essence. Like Foucault's
practices of freedom, the insurrection aims at transforming the
relationship that the individual has with himself. The insurrection
starts, then, with the individual refusing his or her enforced essential
identity: it starts, as Stirner says, from men's discontent with
themselves. Insurrection does not aim at overthrowing political
institutions. It is aimed at the individual, in a sense
transgressing his own identity--the outcome of which is, nevertheless, a
change in political arrangements. Insurrection is therefore not about
becoming what one is--becoming human, becoming man--but about becoming
what one is not.
- This ethos of escaping essential identities through a reinvention
of oneself has many important parallels with the Baudelarian
aestheticization of the self that interests Foucault. Like Baudelaire's assertion that the self must be treated as a
work of art, Stirner sees the self--or the ego--as a "creative
nothingness," a radical emptiness which is up to the individual to
define: "I do not presuppose myself, because I am every moment just
positing or creating myself" (135). The self, for Stirner, is a process,
a continuous flow of self-creating flux--it is a process that eludes the
imposition of fixed identities and essences: "no concept expresses me,
nothing that is designated as my essence exhausts me" (324).
- Therefore, Stirner's strategy of insurrection and
Foucault's project of care for the self are both contingent
practices of freedom that involve a reconfiguration of the subject and
its relationship with the self. For Stirner, as with Foucault, freedom is
an undefined and open-ended project in which the individual engages. The
insurrection, as Stirner argues, does not rely on political institutions
to grant freedom to the individual, but looks to the individual to invent his or her own forms of freedom. It is an attempt to
construct spaces of autonomy within relations of power, by limiting the power that is
exercised over the individual by others and increasing the power that the
individual exercises over himself. The individual, moreover, is free to
reinvent himself in new and unpredictable ways, escaping the limits
imposed by human essence and universal notions of morality.
- The notion of insurrection involves a reformulation of the concept
of freedom in ways that are radically post-Kantian. Stirner suggests, for
instance, that there can be no truly universal idea of freedom; freedom
is always a particular freedom in the guise of the universal. The
universal freedom that, for Kant, is the domain of all rational
individuals, would only mask some hidden particular interest. Freedom,
according to Stirner, is an ambiguous and problematic concept, an
"enchantingly beautiful dream" that seduces the individual yet remains
unattainable, and from which the individual must awaken.
- Furthermore, freedom is a limited concept. It is only seen in its
narrow negative sense. Stirner wants, rather, to extend the concept to a
more positive freedom to. Freedom in the negative sense involves
only self-abnegation--to be rid of something, to deny oneself. That is
why, according to Stirner, the freer the individual ostensibly becomes,
in accordance with the emancipative ideals of Enlightenment humanism, the
more he loses the power he exercises over himself. On the other hand,
positive freedom--or ownness--is a form of freedom that is
invented by the individual for him or herself. Unlike Kantian freedom,
ownness is not guaranteed by universal ideals or categorical imperatives. If it were, it could only lead to further
domination: "The man who is set free is nothing but a freed man [...] he is an unfree man in the
garment of freedom, like the ass in the lion's skin" (152).
- Freedom must, rather, be seized by the individual. For freedom to
have any value it must be based on the power of the individual to create
it. "My freedom becomes complete only when it is my--might; but by this I
cease to be a merely free man, and become and own man" (151). Stirner was
one of the first to recognize that the true basis of freedom is power. To
see freedom as a universal absence of power is to mask its very basis in
power. The theory of ownness is a recognition, and indeed an affirmation, of
the inevitable relation between freedom and power. Ownness is the
realization of the individual's power over himself--the ability to create
his or her own forms of freedom, which are not circumscribed by metaphysical
or essentialist categories. In this sense, ownness is a form of freedom
that goes beyond the categorical imperative. It is based on a notion of
the self as a contingent and open field of possibilities, rather than on
an absolute and dutiful adherence to external moral maxims.
Conclusion
- This idea of ownness is crucial in formulating a post-Kantian
concept of freedom. Perhaps, in Stirner's words, "Ownness created
a new freedom" (147). Firstly, ownness allows freedom to be
considered beyond the limits of universal moral and rational categories.
Ownness is the form of freedom that one invents for oneself, rather than
one that is guaranteed by transcendental ideals. Foucault, too, sought to
"free" freedom from these oppressive limits. Secondly, ownness converges
closely with Foucault's own argument about freedom being situated in
power relations. Like Foucault, Stirner shows that the idea of freedom as
entailing a complete absence of power and constraint is illusory. The
individual is always involved in a complex network of power relations,
and freedom must be fought for, reinvented, and renegotiated within these
limits. Ownness may be seen, then, as creating the possibilities of
resistance to power. Similarly to Foucault, Stirner maintains that
freedom and resistance can always exist, even in the most oppressive
conditions. In this sense, ownness is a project of freedom and resistance
within power's limits--it is the recognition of the fundamentally
antagonistic and ambiguous nature of freedom. Thirdly, not only is
ownness an attempt to limit the domination of the individual, but it is also
a way of intensifying the power that one exercises over oneself. We
have seen that for both Stirner and Foucault, Kant's universal freedom is
based on absolute moral and rational norms that limit individual
sovereignty. Foucault and Stirner are both interested, in different
ways, in reformulating the concept of freedom: through the ethical
practice of care of the self and through the strategy of ownness, both of which are
aimed at increasing the power that the individual has over himself.
- These two strategies allow us to conceptualize freedom in a more
contemporary way. Freedom can no longer be seen as a universal
emancipation, the eternal promise of a world beyond the limits of power.
The freedom that forms the basis of the categorical imperative, the
freedom exalted by Kant as the province of reason and morality, can no
longer serve as the basis for contemporary ideas of freedom. It has been
also shown by Stirner and Foucault to exclude and oppress where it
includes, to enslave where it also liberates. Freedom must be seen as no
longer being subservient to absolute maxims of morality and rationality,
to imperatives that invoke the dull, cold inevitability of law and
punishment. For Stirner and Foucault, freedom must be "freed" from these
absolute notions. Rather than a privilege that is granted from a
metaphysical point to the individual, freedom must be seen as a practice,
a critical ethos of the self, and as a struggle that is engaged in by the
individual within the problematic of power. It necessarily involves a
reflection on the limits of the self and the ontological conditions of
the present--a constant reinvention and problematization of subjectivity.
A post-Kantian freedom, in this way, is not only a recognition of power,
but also a reflection upon power's limits--an affirmation of the
possibilities of individual autonomy within power and of the critical
capacities of modern subjectivity.
Department of Political Science
University of Western Australia
snewman@cyllene.uwa.edu.au
COPYRIGHT (c) 2003 Saul Newman. READERS MAY
USE
PORTIONS OF THIS WORK IN ACCORDANCE WITH THE FAIR USE PROVISIONS OF U.S.
COPYRIGHT LAW. IN ADDITION, SUBSCRIBERS AND MEMBERS OF SUBSCRIBED
INSTITUTIONS MAY
USE THE ENTIRE WORK FOR ANY INTERNAL NONCOMMERCIAL PURPOSE BUT, OTHER THAN
ONE COPY SENT BY EMAIL, PRINT OR FAX TO ONE PERSON AT ANOTHER LOCATION FOR
THAT INDIVIDUAL'S PERSONAL USE, DISTRIBUTION OF THIS ARTICLE OUTSIDE OF A
SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION FROM EITHER THE
AUTHOR OR THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS IS EXPRESSLY FORBIDDEN.
THIS ARTICLE AND OTHER CONTENTS OF THIS ISSUE ARE
AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE UNTIL RELEASE OF THE NEXT ISSUE. A
TEXT-ONLY ARCHIVE OF THE JOURNAL IS ALSO AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE.
FOR FULL HYPERTEXT ACCESS TO BACK ISSUES, SEARCH UTILITIES, AND OTHER
VALUABLE FEATURES, YOU OR YOUR INSTITUTION MAY SUBSCRIBE TO
PROJECT MUSE, THE
ON-LINE JOURNALS PROJECT OF THE
JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS.
Notes
1. See Koch.
2. This rejection of the anthropological
foundations of freedom is also discussed by Rajchman. Indeed Rajchman
sees Foucault's project of freedom as an ethical attitude of continual
questioning of the borders and limits of our contemporary experience--a
freedom of philosophy as well as a philosophy of freedom. My discussion
of Foucault's reconfiguration of the problematic of freedom in terms of
concrete ethical strategies of the self may also be seen in this context.
3. See Lacan. In this essay, Lacan shows
that the Law produces its own transgression, and that it can only operate
through this transgression. The excess of Sade does not contradict the
injunctions, laws, and categorical imperatives of Kant; rather, they are
inextricably linked to it. Like Foucault's discussion of the "spirals" of
power and pleasure, in which power produces the very pleasure it is seen
to repress, Lacan suggests that the denial of enjoyment--embodied in Law,
in the categorical imperative--produces its own form of perverse
enjoyment, or jouissance as a surplus--le plus de
jouir. Sade, according to Lacan, exposes this obscene enjoyment by
reversing the paradigm: he turns this perverse pleasure into a law
itself, into a sort of Kantian categorical imperative or universal
principle: "Let us enunciate the maxim: 'I have the right of enjoyment
over your body, anyone can say to me, and I will exercise this right,
without any limit stopping me in the capriciousness of the exactions that
I might have the taste to satiate'" (58). In this way the obscene pleasure of
the Law that is unmasked in Kant is reversed into the Law of obscene
pleasure through Sade. As Zizek remarks in "Kant with (or against)
Sade," the crucial insight of Lacan's argument here is not that Kant is a
closet sadist, but rather that Sade is a "closet Kantian." That is,
Sadean excess is taken to such an extreme that it becomes emptied of
pleasure and takes the form of a cold-blooded, joyless universal Law.
Works Cited
Custer, Olivia. "Exercising Freedom: Kant and Foucault." Philosophy
Today 42 (1989): 137-146.
Feuerbach, Ludwig. The Essence of Christianity. New York:
Harper, 1957.
Foucault, Michel. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the
Prison. Trans. Alan Sheridan. London: Penguin, 1977. 195-228.
---. "The Ethics of the Concern for the Self as a Practice of Freedom." Ethics: Subjectivity and
Truth. Essential Works of Michel Foucault, 1954-1984. Ed. Paul
Rabinow. Trans. Robert J. Hurley. Vol. 1. London: Penguin, 1997. 281-301.
---. "Intellectual and Power: A Conversation between Michel Foucault and
Gilles Deleuze." Foucault, Language 204-217.
---. "Kant on Enlightenment and Revolution." Trans. Colin Gordon.
Economy and Society 15.1 (1986): 88-96.
---. Language, Counter-Memory, Practice: Selected Essays and
Interviews. Ed. Donald Bouchard. Oxford: Blackwell, 1977. 204-217.
---. "Revolutionary Action: 'Until Now.'" Foucault, Language
218-233.
---. "The Subject and Power." Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism
and Hermeneutics. By Hubert L. Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow. Chicago:
U of Chicago P, 1982. 208-226.
---. The Use of Pleasure: The History of Sexuality, Volume
2. Trans. Robert Hurley. New York: Pantheon, 1985. 29-30.
---. "What is Enlightenment?" The Foucault Reader. Ed. Paul
Rabinow. New York: Pantheon, 1984. 32-50.
Gordon, Colin. "Question, Ethos, Event: Foucault on Kant and the
Enlightenment." Economy and Society 15.1 (1986): 71-87.
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Practical Reason. Trans. Thomas
Kingsmill Abbot. London: Longmans, 1963.
Koch, Andrew. "Max Stirner: The Last Hegelian or the First
Poststructuralist." Anarchist Studies 5 (1997): 95-107.
Lacan, Jacques. "Kant with Sade." October 51 (1989): 55-75.
Rajchman, John. Michel Foucault: The Freedom of Philosophy.
New York: Columbia UP, 1985.
Stirner, Max. The Ego and Its Own. Trans. David Leopold.
Cambridge and London: U of Cambridge P, 1995.
Zizek, Slavoj. "Kant with (or against) Sade." The Zizek
Reader. Eds. Elizabeth Wright and Edmond Wright. Oxford:
Blackwell, 1999.
|