-
The increasing political presence of refugees and immigrants in post-Cold war Europe has generated considerable debate about
the nature of multicultural society. The demand for the recognition of cultural, racial, and ethnic differences has come to
occupy a central place in the forms of post-national politics emergent today. Yet, a closer examination of the
juridico-political regulations developed in response to these demands reveals a troubling tendency: cultural/racial difference
is translated into an understanding of cultural diversity that treats minorities, to use David Bennett's term, as "add-ons"
(5) to the existing nation form. Thus the question becomes whether such an "additive model" (5) is capable of
inducing a radical transformation in the concept of the sovereign position of the national self. This essay addresses the
limitations of this procedural multiculturalist valorization and argues that the liberal imperative to tolerate and respect
cultural difference is far from displacing the sovereignty of the host society in question. In discussing these limitations, I
will situate liberal multiculturalism in the context of today's capitalist globalization.
-
When we examine the policies and programs through which the culturally different is valorized today, it becomes clear that
liberalism has become the regulative principle in many metropolitan countries. Yet it is far from clear whether such a liberal
valorization and the granting of legal rights to non-normative citizens, the ethnically and racially "different," will prove to
be a counter-hegemonic political force. Is the legal codification of respect for identities in their
particularity adequate for reinventing a democratic political space? If such politicization does not flourish in
particularist liberal multiculturalism, then we need to be vigilant about what is being left intact. In fact, we need to take
our vigilance one step further and question the ways in which such codification regulates the destabilizing force of the
political and entails its repudiation, suspension, limitation, or foreclosure.
-
We are witnessing an increasing proliferation of literature trying to
understand the new economic, political, and cultural arrangements that are
inaugurated by global capital. The accelerating rate of the international
division of labor, the extended capacity of multinational production, the
development and concentration of global financial and banking services
and culture industries, the rapid development in telecommunications, and
the growth of a global mass culture have led many to talk about a process
by which the world is now becoming a single and unified space.
Globalization, according to the advocates of this position, marks the
beginning of a process whereby difference is dissolved within the logic
of sameness and cultural homogenization. Consequently we are reminded of
the hazards and shortcomings of limiting our inquiries with nations and
nation-states, for the sovereignty of nation-states has been declared to
be undermined in the age of cultural, economic, social homogeneity, and
integration.
-
On the other side of the debate, there are those who emphasize the
impossibility of envisioning a unified global culture. For example, in
"Disjuncture and Difference in the Global Cultural Economy,"
Arjun Appadurai suggests
that when forces are brought from various metropoles into different
societies they tend to become indigenized in some way. To understand the
complexity of the process of globalization, he suggests that we examine
the fundamental disjunctures between economy, politics, and culture. For
Appadurai the global cultural flows occur in and through the disjunctures
between five "scapes": ethnoscapes, mediascapes, technoscapes,
finanscapes, and ideoscapes. Such disjunctures and flows point not only to
the fluid and irregular nature of international capital but also
constitute the building blocks of the replacement of Benedict Anderson's
"imagined community" with "imagined worlds."
-
Those who, like Appadurai, are critical of the global homogenization argument suggest that the globalized world is a contested
and contradictory space. These critics point to the increasing proliferation of ethnic and racial struggle to argue that the
homogenizing pressure of globalization paradoxically produces cultural heterogeneity. It is the encounter of the local with
the global that is deemed to force the recognition of alternative histories, traditions, and cultures that have hitherto
remained silent under the ruins of the project of modernity and colonialism. For example, Ulf Hannerz, in "Cosmopolitans and
Locals in World Culture," points out that cultural differences now exist not between cultures but within cultures and
suggests that world culture implies a reorganization of diversity rather than a replication of uniformity. It is no longer
possible to talk about the homogenization of systems of meaning; between the different regions of the globe there are now
flows of
meanings, people, and goods. The globe can be imagined as a homogenized unity only when localities are discarded and when power
relations among its constituting parts are ignored.
-
Thus globalization increasingly reveals the limits of Western modernity: various ethnic and racial minorities, their
traditions, memories, myths, and symbols are now woven together in the increasingly dense web of metropolitan culture. In an
attempt to understand how particularity and difference are articulated in this global culture, Stuart Hall, in "The Local and
the Global," questions attributing a singular and unitary logic to capital. The notion of the global which is capable of
getting hold of and neutralizing everybody and everything and thereby contains all marginality in an uncontradictory and
uncontested space does not accurately capture the specificity of this decentralized and de-centered form of globalization.
Hall suggests that with the accelerating rate of migration, older unitary cultural formations are now breaking down. The
emergent form of globalization simultaneously valorizes the local and the global. Hall does not deny the homogenizing form of
this new cultural representation, but he argues that it is a peculiar form of homogenization--one that simultaneously absorbs
and recognizes difference. This form of global homogenization does not obliterate difference but rather works in and through
difference. While capital is spreading globally, it works through specificity. Although the growing global culture is now
located in the West and speaks English, it is increasingly invaded by other languages and accents. It is therefore forced to
negotiate and incorporate a difference that it formerly tried to conquer. In a paradoxical turn, as minorities reclaim
representation for themselves, marginality has been turned into a powerful space. The identities that have hitherto been
excluded now signal the emergence of new subjects, new ethnicities, and new communities, and they have acquired the means to
speak
for themselves. Although Hall acknowledges that resorting to such localities by retreating into exclusivist and defensive
enclaves might become dangerous and can lead to forms of fundamentalism, he nevertheless thinks that ethnicity is the
necessary position of enunciation from which the formerly excluded marginality speaks and grounds itself.
-
As is clear from this brief review of current critical discourse, one of the characterizing features of the debate on
globalization is the opposition between homogenization and heterogenization or between
universalization and particularization. Moreover, the particular or
different is presumed to be endowed with some resistive and liberative
capacity in the face of the universalizing tendency of global capital. I
would suggest that this is a misleading opposition as it identifies
globalization with universalization[1]
and consequently locates the counter-hegemonic political struggle against
the global force of capital in the affirmation of particular identities.
In "A Leftist Plea for Eurocentrism," Slavoj Zizek rightly points out that it is
deeply misleading to posit the rising globalization in opposition to
particular identities since the true opposition is between globalization
and universalism. For him, the new world is global but not universal; it is an order, which, rather than
negating the particular, allocates each and every particular a place.[2] Therefore, what is threatened by globalization is not particularity but
universality itself. Universalism, for Zizek, is the "properly
political domain" as it implies "universalizing one's particular fate
as representative of global injustice" (1007). If we want to go beyond
the rather simplistic praising of the particular, one of the tasks that
awaits us is to develop a conceptual framework that will allow us to
rethink globalization and the apparent counter-tendency of valorization
of particular identities as a double gesture of capital. What needs to be
questioned is whether the particular that is valorized in
multiculturalist politics constitutes a destabilizing political force in
the wake of global abstraction of transnational capitalism which now
operates completely divorced from its specific origins in Europe, as
Dirlik argues in "The Global in the Local," and whose immanent logic
remains indifferent to the boundaries of the nation-state, as Zizek
suggests in "Multiculturalism, or, the Cultural Logic of Multinational
Capitalism."
-
The decentering of capitalism, its deterritorialization and abstraction, implies the difficulty of pointing to any nation or
region as the center of global capitalism. This has led many to emphasize the qualitatively different nature of global
capitalism
from its earlier forms. For Dirlik, this qualitative difference of global capitalism can be discerned in the authentic global
abstraction capitalism has achieved, in the decentering and production of networks of urban formations without a clearly
definable center--a network which is then relinked via transnational corporations (30). Likewise, in
"Ambiguous Universality," Etienne Balibar delineates the transformations created in the geographical and geopolitical pattern
of the world and points to the multiplication of centers, which form a network rather than a "core" area (52). Similarly,
Zizek suggests that the final moment of capitalism entails the cutting of the umbilical cord of global companies with their
mother-nation. It is thus no longer possible to pin down a colonizing agency as in the case of traditional imperialist
colonialism. The paradox of this form of colonization resides in the fact that it takes place without a colonizing
nation-state, as the colonizing agents now become the global companies themselves ("Multiculturalism" 43-52). Dirlik finds the
concern with the local in the wake of global capitalism ironic for the following reason: while disorganizing earlier forms and
reconfiguring global relations, global capitalism enhances an awareness of the local so as to be able to render the local
manipulable in its hands, pointing to it as the site of resistance to capital (35). Therefore the privileging of
the local without the recognition of this context and the concomitant ideological criticism of global capitalism voiced from
the presumably resistive site of the local falls prey to the ideological legitimization of the structures which are indeed the
very production of global capitalism. For Dirlik, the limitations of such criticism stem from the fact that global
capitalism leaves no local that is not already worked over, continually disorganized, reconstituted, or assimilated as part of
its universalizing and homogenizing operations (37).
-
What do we make of the growing liberal multiculturalist dictum to respect
and tolerate the racially, culturally, and ethnically different in the
wake of the tendency of capital for global abstraction? Can these two
trends be regarded as contradictory? In other words, does multiculturalist
tolerance for difference, which not only acknowledges the value of each
and every group's cultural characteristics but also tries to amend the
wrong each one of them is subjected to through various juridical and
legal procedures, signal the emergence of a counter-political force
against the global hegemony of capital?
-
Slavoj Zizek, in his reading of the three different meanings of
universality distinguished by Balibar, sees multiculturalist tolerance,
respect and protection of human rights, democracy, and so forth as the
hegemonic fiction of the real universality of today's globalization.
("Multiculturalism" 41). The concrete universality of global order is
supplanted by allowing each particular lifestyle to flourish in its
particularity. For Zizek, the modern era, whose predominant form of
concrete universality is the nation-state, worked by seizing the
individual directly, restraining his or her freedom as the citizen of a
nation-state. Against the de-nationalization of the ethnic into the
national of the modern period, the intensification of global market
forces entails the ethnicization of the national and renewed
reconstitution of ethnic roots. Respect and tolerance for the
ethnically different is a reaction to the universal dimension of the
world market and hence occurs against its background and on its very
terrain (42). Multiculturalism, in Zizek's formulation, is the form of
the appearance of universality in its exact mirror opposite and is therefore
the ideal form of the ideology of global capitalism. In A Critique of
Postcolonial Reason, Gayatri Spivak also points to the bond
between liberal multiculturalism and global capitalism. She suggests that
"liberal multiculturalism is determined by the demands of contemporary
transnational capitalisms" (397) which secure the means of gaining the
consent of developing nations in the financialization of the globe.
-
Perhaps the originality of Zizek's argument does not lie in the link he
establishes between multiculturalism and the interests of global
capitalism. Spivak, Jameson, Dirlik and Hall, in their different ways, have developed similar arguments. But
there is more to Zizek's formulation. Focusing his attention particularly
on the implications of the notions of respect and tolerance, he suggests
that multiculturalism entails a Eurocentric distance when it
respects and tolerates the local and particular cultures (44). In this sense,
multiculturalism is based on a disavowed and inverted self-referential
form of racism as it empties its own position of all positive content.
The racism of multiculturalism does not reside in its being against the
values of other cultures. Quite the contrary: it respects and tolerates
other cultures, but in respecting and tolerating the different, it
maintains a distance which enables it to retain a privileged position of
empty universality. It is this emptied universal position which enables
one to appreciate (or depreciate) other local cultures. Thus
multiculturalist respect for the particularity of the other is indeed a
form of asserting one's own superiority and sovereignty. As David Lloyd
cogently describes in "Race under Representation," the alleged neutrality
and universality is at the same time a process that secures a sovereign
status for the subject:
The position occupied by the dominant individual is that of the Subject
without properties. The Subject with "unlimited properties" is precisely
the undetermined subject . . . Its universality is attained by virtue of
literal indifference: this Subject becomes representative in consequence
of being able to take anyone's place, of occupying any place, of a pure
exchangeability. Universal where all others are particular, partial, this
Subject is the perfect, disinterested judge formed for and by the public
sphere. (70)
- In Colonial Fantasies: Towards a Feminist Reading of
Orientalism, I have suggested that it is the centering of the
self, which, by setting itself off from the particular, allows its
universalizing gesture (103). But, as Zizek suggests, the critical task
here is not to expose the truth of multiculturalism, which is presumed to
be the concealment of particular roots behind the mask of universality.
Rather, the problematic of multiculturalism, premised on the hybrid
co-existence of diverse cultural forms, "is the form of appearance of its
opposite, of the massive presence of capitalism as universal
world system; it bears witness to the unprecedented homogenization of the
contemporary world" ("Multiculturalism" 45). Therefore, for Zizek, "the
true horror does not reside in the particular content hidden beneath the
universality of global Capital, but rather in the fact that Capital is
effectively an anonymous global machine blindly running its course, that
there is effectively no particular Secret Agent who animates it" (46).
Precisely for this reason, the fight for cultural difference and respect
for minorities leaves the basic universalizing operation of global
capitalism unharmed and intact and hence needs to be seen as symptomatic
of the suffocation and regulation of "politics proper" ("A Leftist
Plea" 988-999).[3] The task, therefore,
is to understand the mechanisms by which this regulation, suffocation, and
foreclosure are managed. If the institutionalized multiculturalist pluralism
that characterizes the post-national global order implies a foreclosure
of politics proper and is far from offering a potential for
democratic politicization, then where do we locate the possibility of a
politics that interrupts this foreclosure? To discuss this, allow me to
make a detour through Jacques Derrida's argument concerning
conditional and unconditional hospitality.
HOSPITALITY AS LAW
- In Adieu to Emmanuel Levinas, Derrida reads Kant's
writings on cosmopolitan law and draws our attention to his essay "Toward
Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Project," particularly the "Third
Definitive Article for a Perpetual Peace" which pertains to the "right of
hospitality": "The Law of World Citizenship Shall be Limited to
Conditions of Universal Hospitality." Derrida notes that this article is
limited by a number of conditions. From the very beginning we are
confronted with the question of conditional hospitality. The
question of hospitality in Kant's writings pulls us into the domain of
law, citizenship and the relation the state has with its subjects.
Universal hospitality here is only juridical and political. Cosmopolitan
law is about international agreement and refers to the condition of
justice and law that is to be decided by nations. Hospitality is treated
as a question of rights, justice and obligation that is to be
regulated by law.[4] Resting on
a juridical and political definition, the Kantian formulation is based
not on granting the right of residence but only the right of temporary
sojourn. As a juridical regulation, it concerns the rights of citizens of
states that are to be regulated and deliberated by a cosmopolitical
constitution. As such, it suspends and conditions the immediate, infinite, and unconditional welcoming of the other (87).
-
Derrida directs our attention to the fact that conditional hospitality is
offered at the owner's place, home, nation, state, or city--that is, at a
place where one is defined as the master and where unconditional
hospitality or unconditional trespassing of the door is not possible. The
host, the non-guest, the one who accepts, the one who offers hospitality,
the one who welcomes, is the owner of a home and therefore is the master
of the home.[5]
-
As I mentioned above, Derrida directs our attention to the fact that in
Kant's essay, hospitality is framed as a question of law, an obligation,
a duty, and a right: it refers to the welcoming of an alien/stranger other
as a non-enemy. The formulation of hospitality as a question of law
weaves it with contradiction because the welcoming of the other within
the limits of law is possible on the condition that the host, the owner
of the home, the one who accepts, remains the master of the home and
thereby retains his/her authority in that place. The law of
hospitality is the law of oikonomia, the law of one's home.
Offered as the law of place, hospitality lays down the limits of a place
and retains the authority over that place, thus limiting the gift that is
offered, retaining the self as self in one's own home as the
condition of hospitality. In making this the condition of hospitality,
it affirms the law of the same. Hospitality is a giving gesture. But with
the hospitality as law, what this gesture in fact does is to subject the
stranger/foreigner to the law of the host's home. In this way, the
foreigner is allowed to enter the host's space under conditions the host has determined. Hence conditional welcoming entails
a way of insinuating a place from which one invites the other and hence lays down the
conditions for "appropriating for oneself a place to welcome the other,
or, worse, welcoming the other in order to appropriate for oneself a place
and then speak the language of hospitality" (15-6). Therefore the law
of hospitality is characterized by a limitation. The host affirms
the position of a master in his/her own home; in the space and things
he/she provides to the stranger/guest, the host assures his/her
sovereignty and says: this space belongs to me; we are in my home.
Welcome to me. Feel at home but on the condition that you obey the rules
of hospitality (14). This gesture affirms one's sovereignty and
one's being at one's own home. For this reason, hospitality as
law limits itself with a threshold.[6]
-
Drawing on Derrida's deconstructive reading of the contradictions inherent in conditional hospitality, we can suggest that
multiculturalist tolerance of minorities within the host nation-state is not for nothing. Welcoming the other in the form of
codified multiculturalist tolerance implies a conditional welcoming, as the hospitality offered remains limited within law and
jurisdiction. But more importantly, this kind of tolerance does not result in a fundamental modification of the host subject's
mode of inhabiting the territory that is deemed to be solely within his/her possession. Far from laying the grounds for an
interruption of sovereign identity of the self, multiculturalist respect and tolerance implies the conditional welcoming of
the guest within the prescribed limits of the law and hence implies a reassertion of mastery over the national space as it
enables the subject to appropriate a place for itself--an empty and universal and therefore sovereign place--from which the
other is welcomed. Thus the place from which multiculturalist tolerance welcomes the particularity of the other, fortified by
codifications such as affirmative action and other legal measures, is what precisely enables the disavowed and inverted
self-referentiality of racist hospitality which by emptying the host's position from any positive content asserts its
superiority and sovereignty.
-
The inherent paradox of multiculturalism's conditional and lawful welcoming of the other as guest can be productively
understood as conforming to "the structure of exception" that Giorgio Agamben discusses in Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power
and Bare Life. In discussing this, I want to refer to the German case where the paradox of the inclusion of minorities
within the limits of law can be illustrated. All of the laws that regulate the conditions of arrival, presence, and departure
of "guest-workers" in Germany reveal that the overriding concern is that of recruitment of a short-term labor force. For this
reason, residence permits are conferred only as work permits. Laws explicitly anticipate that the workers will leave Germany
when the needs of capital are fulfilled. The fact that the workers' presence is regarded
as temporary
makes clear that the new regulations are seen as an exception: a parenthesis to be opened and eventually closed. The logic
underlying these laws is that the acceptance/welcoming of foreign labor is a conditional one, as the workers' presence, which
is expected to be temporary, is deemed to be an exception to the general rule. Tellingly, the term "migrant" is not typically
used to name this group. As
guests,
these workers are accepted as an exception to the general rule of membership in the German polity. Their welcoming is not
regulated within the framework of the general rule of law. In accordance with the persistent and widespread sentiment
that declares that "Germany is not a land of immigration," the conditional welcoming or the temporary hosting of foreign labor
appears at first glance to be set outside the purview of general law. Hence these regulations are nothing but the name of an
interim, an exception.
-
Following Agamben, we can ask whether as an exception, the conditional
welcoming of workers indicates that they are left outside the sovereign
law of the host society? It is clear that this temporary foreign labor
force has been included in the German territory without being turned into
proper members of the polity. Their membership is undecidable from the
perspective of the German self and law since their inclusion exceeds
membership, testifying to the impasse of a system based on law, which is
incapable of making their inclusion coincide with membership. As guests
having temporary abode, they are not properly inside. But does this
indicate that they are outside the purview of sovereign and general law?
One way to approach this dynamic between outside and inside is to see
them as a limit figure which brings into crisis the clear
distinction between what is inside and what is outside. Surely this not
an altogether invalid way of grasping the dynamic between the guest and
the host that is structured through the law, but it is a limited one insofar as the paradox of exception is concerned.
-
Exception, Agamben notes, "embodies a kind of membership without inclusion" (24).
What defines the German sovereign claim of ownership of the land can be
understood with Agamben's following remarks: "what defines the
character of the sovereign claim is precisely that it applies to the
exception in no longer applying to it, that it includes what is outside
itself . . . . What cannot be included in any way is included in the form of
the exception" (24). It seems that we can talk about a paradoxical
inclusion of guest-workers, which is indeed an "inclusive exclusion"
(21). For Agamben, the regulation that is exercised by the law is
achieved not by a command or prescription, but by the creation of "the
sphere of its own reference in real life and make that reference regular"
(26). The sovereign claim of the general law is constituted by having a
grip over the exception and by articulating it into its domain through an
inclusive exclusion. It is through the exception, through the
inclusive exclusion of the exception, that the law is able to generate and
cultivate itself. The apparent exclusion of the exception is in fact an
indication of its paradoxical inclusion in the juridical order.
-
For Agamben, when we see exception as fundamental to the structure of the
constitution of sovereignty, then sovereignty can be grasped neither as
an exclusively political nor as a juridical category; it is not "a power
external to law (Schmitt)" or to the supreme rule of juridical order (Hans Kelsen): it is the originary
structure in which law refers to life and includes it in itself by
suspending it" (28). Following Jean-Luc Nancy's suggestion, he gives the
name ban to "this potentiality . . . of the law to maintain itself
in its own privation, to apply in no longer applying" (28). The law, in
excluding or banning, does not place the exception to its exteriority,
but abandons or threatens it on a threshold where the distinction between
outside and inside, life and law, becomes blurred. It becomes difficult to
say in a definite manner whether the one who is banned is outside or
inside the juridical order. The paradox of sovereignty is that it leaves
nothing outside the law as it has a hold on life even when it abandons
what it interdicts.
-
In offering hospitality that is conditional, the German national self
appropriates a place for himself/herself so as to be able to say welcome.
This entails not only maintaining the status of the German national self as
master, but more importantly it institutes a welcoming in order to
nourish the sovereignty of the German subject that was already in place.
To understand the dynamic that is operating here, we can establish a link
between Derrida's understanding of "conditional hospitality" and what
Agamben calls "inclusive exclusion." Though pushed outside, the
provisional acceptance of the guest-workers enables the regeneration and
nourishment of the German national self, which needs to reconstitute its
sovereignty each time anew. Such a sovereign self maintains and nurtures
itself not by pushing particular others to its exteriority or outside
the purview of general law. On the contrary, it is their inclusive
exclusion, which the conditional welcoming enables, that is indispensable
for a reassertion of a sovereign German national self. The empty and
universal position of the sovereign claim enabled by the general rule of law
is capable of instituting conditional hospitality as an
exception and this enables the means to codify respect and
tolerance for the different and confer upon them rights in the form of
law. It is precisely at this point that we need to be vigilant and
to problematize this codification by asking what is being negated and
foreclosed here. Does this codification entail the opening of the space
of politics or does it effectively signal the circumscription of what
Zizek calls "politics proper" or what Antonio Negri calls "constituent
power"?
POLITICS
- In his discussion of the three forms of universality, Balibar gives the proposition concerning human rights as the
example of ideal universality (65). Reversing the
traditional relationship between subjection and citizenship, ideal
universality justifies the universal extension of political (civic)
rights by explaining that equality and liberty are inseparable, which
Balibar calls "equaliberty." As such, it introduces the notion of
unconditional into the realm of politics: "equaliberty is an
all-or-nothing" notion and hence cannot be relativized. It is either
recognized or ignored as a principle or as a demand. Balibar links this
characteristic of equaliberty to what Hannah Arendt calls "the right to
have rights," which is distinct from having this or that specific right
that is guaranteed by law. Nor is it a moral notion. It is a political
notion and delineates a process, which starts with resistance and ends
with the actual exercise of constituent power (66). For this reason, for
Balibar, the "right to have rights" can also be called the "right to have
politics." As an unconditional force, the demand for equaliberty sets in
motion a permanent insurrection that can never be gentrified or
"fully integrated into the harmonious whole of the concrete universality"
(65). But does this mean that constituent power, as the irreducible
excess (to use Zizek's formulation), is allowed to exercise its full
destabilizing potential of the political? Certainly not. The question thus becomes: what
are the means through which this insurrectionary demand is domesticated, suffocated, limited,
regulated, neutralized, or congealed?
- To answer this question--to understand the dynamic by which the "right to have rights" or the "right to have
politics" of minorities and foreigners is regulated and hence limited through institutionalized multiculturalism and through
the granting of a set of rights guaranteed by law--it is useful to turn to (and to revise) Antonio Negri's conception of
constituent and constitutive power as articulated in Insurgencies:
Constituent Power and the Modern State. I have already
suggested, following Zizek, that it is through liberal multiculturalist institutional and
juridical regulations that the post-national global order renders its global universalizing tendency indiscernible and
thereby forecloses the possibility for a right to have politics or democratic
politics. But does the current global management of the conditional and
legal hosting of immigrants mean that any change in the law or
any attempt to modify the law will by definition play into the hands
of the forces of globalization? Can the legal conditions of hospitality or laws on
immigration be improved? The analysis that Negri offers regarding the relation
between constitutive and constituent power seems to imply that any attempt to improve or change the law is a vain effort;
that it's futile to attempt to replace existing laws with better ones, for any politics that remains within the
purview of law is doomed to fail as it implies suffocation of democratic
politics through constitutional arrangements. After a brief discussion of
the analysis Negri offers and its limitations, I will discuss Derrida's
deconstructive reading of the relation between law and
justice on the one hand and conditional and
unconditional hospitality on the other hand and suggest that the
latter offers a radically different opening of politics.[7]
-
For Negri, to speak of constituent power is to speak of
democracy for it is constituent power that regulates democracy. It is not
only all-powerful, but also has an expansive and unlimited quality. It
emerges from the vortex of the void and is characterized by the openness
of its needs and the absence of determinations and finalities. Its strength
lies in the fact that it never ends up in power, nor its multitude
results in a totality. As an open multiplicity, it is always based upon a
set of singularities. Its all-powerful and expansive tendency, its
strength, which opens a horizon, never results in a vertical or
totalitarian dimension. The active elements of constituent power are
resistance, desire, and an ethical impulse. It does not seek
institutionality but aims at constructing an ethical being. It
is for these reasons that Negri emphasizes the
strong link between constituent power and democracy. Democracy is the
political form of constituent power. The concept of democracy in Negri's
formulation is not treated as a subspecies or a subcategory of liberalism
but refers to a form of governability that enables the freeing of
constituent power, because it entails a totality without a closure and
the exclusion of any sign of external definition. It is a project of the
multitude and is a creative force. This multitude is not an ungraspable
multiplicity but is the strength of singularities and differences. As a
singular multidirectionality it refers to an irreducible concept of the
political and to an ethics that recognizes singularities. Like democracy,
constituent power resists being constitutionalized.
-
The opposite of democracy and constituent power is not
totalitarianism but sovereignty itself and
constitutional power. The establishment of constitutional power presents
a closure to the always-open nature of constituent power. When
constituent power is articulated in juridical definitions, it is limited,
closed, reduced to juridical categories, and is restrained in
administrative routines. The State's constitutionality and its various
other regulatory activities bring a form of control, well-defined limits, and procedures to the all-expansive force of the
constituent power. Once it is situated in the concept of the nation and absorbed by the mechanism
of representation, constituent power is perverted, desiccated, congealed
in a static system. Representation is one of the fundamental
juridical-constitutional instruments in exercising control and in
segmenting constituent power. Its dilution in representative mechanisms
manifests itself in political space but is disguised in the activity of the
Supreme Court and other organs of the State. These mechanisms restore traditional sovereignty and close the possibility of
democratic innovation. The taming and suffocation of constituent power
by constitutionalist arrangements entails the mediation of inequalities
and hence the neutralization of its strength. The fixing and
institutionalization of constituent power implies its de facto
termination and negation. And in this way, the sovereignty inverts the
ostensible foundation of democratic polity and reconstructs itself as the foundation.
-
Although Negri's analysis of the ways in which constitutive power tames
and suffocates constituent power is a useful one to think how laws of
conditional hospitality limit the unconditional welcoming of foreigners,
it nevertheless suffers from certain limitations. Negri does not use the concept of constituent power as a theoretical or
philosophical device that enables him to better understand how constitutive arrangements limit a more expansive politics.
Rather, he treats constituent power as something that can actually be established as such by its affirmation or as a
self-affirming power. Moreover, Negri posits the relation between constitutive and constituent power as an opposition or a
dialectical contradiction; he poses the relation between constitutive and constituent power as an either/or question. The
heterogeneity between the two is reduced to an antinomy. As such, his analysis risks leaving intact the very structure it
aims to criticize; it risks repeating the same desire for a sovereign position, shifted now to the side of the hegemonized
second term.
-
In an attempt to rethink another philosophical and theoretical framework
that might help us to envision the possibility of reinventing a political
space that is neither locked within the limits and congealments of
conditional hospitality nor one that pretends to go beyond the law by
simply reversing it, I want to discuss Derrida's reading of the relation
between conditional and conditional hospitality and law and justice.
ETHICS OF HOSPITALITY AND THE POSSIBILITY OF DEMOCRATIC POLITICS
- How does Derrida think the relationship between conditional and
unconditional hospitality? Are they mutually exclusive of each other and
hence standing in a relation of opposition? Does unconditional hospitality
simply imply that nation-states make it their official
policy and open their borders and unconditionally welcome anyone who
wants to come? Does it have the status of a regulative idea and hence constitute the name of a correct politics? Or does it have
the status of a deconstructive tool devised to read the limits of conditional
hospitality?
-
While Kant is concerned with hospitality as law and thereby with the
conditions and limitations of hospitality, Levinas engages with it as a
question of ethics or as the question of ethicity itself. In his
reading of Levinas's formulation of the ethics of hospitality, Derrida
orients our attention to the fact that in the lawful admittance of the
other as guest there is a level that exceeds and hence cannot be captured
by those analyses that take the nation-state and the juridical regulation
as the model to work on. Or rather, his question is whether the ethics of
hospitality, in Levinas's thought, is conducive for "a law and a politics beyond the familial dwelling, within a society,
nation, State, or Nation-State" (Adieu 20). It is this level that Derrida's
reading of Levinas's ethics of hospitality brings to the fore.
-
Pointing to a hiatus between the law and ethics of hospitality, Derrida
underlines how the ethics of hospitality cannot be treated as a decree
nor can it be imposed by a command. The hiatus between the law and ethics
of hospitality also pertains to the fact that it is unthematizable,
implying that a particular law or politics of hospitality cannot be
deduced from Levinas's discourse of the ethics of hospitality, for it is
irreducible to a theme, thematization, or some kind of formalization.
Ethics as such is an attentive intention, a welcome and tending
toward the other, an unconditional "yes" to the other. Hospitality as
ethicity is infinite (it is either infinite, unconditional or
not at all) and cannot be limited in the sense that Kant talks about
it; it cannot be regulated by a particular political or juridical
practice of a nation and therefore cannot be circumscribed.
-
Derrida notes that the ethics of hospitality, the welcome made to the
other, entails the subordination or putting in question of the freedom of
the subject and an interruption of the self as other. But this
interruption is not something that can be enforced by a decree or law. It
is an interruption produced in the intentional attention to the other.
The subordination of the freedom of the subject does not imply depriving
the subject of its birth. Rather it implies the subjection of the
subjectum and enables the birth of the subject along with freedom:
the coming of the subject to itself as it welcomes the other.
Responsibility for the other, the being-host of the subject, puts the subject into question; it puts the subject's being in
question. Therefore, for Derrida, "the host is a hostage insofar as he is a subject
put into question, obsessed (and thus besieged), persecuted in the very
place where he takes place, where as emigrant, exile, stranger, a guest
from the very beginning, he finds himself elected to or taken up by a
residence before himself electing or taking one up" (20).
-
Unconditional hospitality entails a reversal, since the owner of the home
can perform hospitality on the condition that she is invited to
her own home by the one whom she invites, by being welcomed,
accepted by the one whom she welcomes or accepts, and shown
hospitality in her own home by the guest. Unconditional hospitality
or hospitality as ethics implies the interruption of a full possession of
a place called home and when its inhabitant becomes a guest received in
her home--that is, when the owner becomes a tenant in her place.
The inexorable law of hospitality therefore involves a situation in which
the hote who receives (the host), the one who welcomes the
invited or received hote (the guest), the welcoming
hote who considers himself the owner of the place, is in truth a
hote received in his own home. He receives the hospitality that he offers
in his own home; he receives it from his own home--which, in the end, does
not belong to him. The hote as host is a guest. The dwelling
opens itself to itself, to its "essence" without essence, as a "land of asylum or
refuge." The one who welcomes is first welcomed in his own home. The one
who invites is invited by the one whom he invites. The one who receives
is received, receiving hospitality in what he takes to be his own home,
or indeed his own land . . . . (41-2)
- Hospitality in this sense precedes property, since home, in this
unconditional welcoming, is not owned, or is owned only in a very
singular sense. That is, only insofar it is already hospitable to its
owner, when the master of the house is already a received hote
or a guest in her own home. When home is no longer a property but a
place that welcomes its owner, the question of hospitality cannot be
reduced to a multiculturalist tolerance, for there is no longer a question
of limiting, restricting, or regulating tolerance for the other. As
Derrida puts it:
That a people, as a people, "should accept those who come and settle
among them--even though they are foreigners," would be the proof
[gage] of a popular and public commitment [engagement],
a political res publica that cannot be reduced to a sort of
"tolerance," unless this tolerance requires the affirmation of a "love"
without measure. (Adieu 72)
In the hospitality without conditions, the host should, in
principle, receive even before knowing anything about the guest. A pure
welcome consists not only in not knowing anything or acting as if one
knows nothing, but also in avoiding any questions about the Other's
identity, their desire, their rules, their language, their capacity for
work, for integration, for adaptation . . . From the moment that I
formulate all of these questions, and posit these conditions . . . the ideal
situation of non-knowledge--non-savoir--is
broken--rompue. ("A Discussion" 9)
-
Above I have delineated the characterizing features of what unconditional
hospitality is. To be able to understand its relation to conditional
hospitality, I want to briefly review how Derrida understands the relation
between law and justice in "Force of Law: The 'Mystical Foundation of
Authority,'" as it has a parallel structure with conditional and
unconditional hospitality. This will enable us to better comprehend the
nature of the relation between conditional and unconditional hospitality
and thus better understand how unconditional hospitality is not simply the name of a political program.
-
For Derrida, there lies an aporia within the drive for justice because it has to respect universality on the one hand
and absolute singularity on the other. One faces difficulty in justice precisely because of the necessity to speak in terms of
the universal principles when one is deciding about particular cases. Since law includes these two conditions simultaneously,
the singularity has to be translated into universality. The aporia resides in the principle of universality which
cannot directly speak to the particular case: in the fact that it is not possible to be just for everyone and for every single
case. This is what Derrida means in saying that "justice is impossible." However, justice is the principle in the name of
which law is deconstructed; that is, it is possible to change and improve the law, the legal system. Law can be criticized and
therefore is deconstructible, but justice is not deconstructible. Thus despite the absolute radical heterogeneity between the
two, the relation between them is not one of opposition. Law is not opposed to justice, nor is justice opposed to law. Derrida
makes clear that justice and law are indissociable because it is in the name of justice that one deconstructs the
law. The relation between them will remain endlessly open and irreducible. To tend to justice one has to deconstruct and
improve the law, but it is never just--and it is there, in the space between law and justice, that one negotiates
between the universal and the particular.
-
Like justice, unconditional hospitality is also impossible. But this
impossibility does not mean that one does not aspire to pure
hospitality. Its impossibility lies in the very structure of
unconditional hospitality itself. In principle, it is offered to an
unlimited number of Others and to an unlimited extent, without asking any
questions. The Other's welcoming is not to be contingent upon the Other's
identity or the questions asked. The very notion of pure or unconditional
hospitality assumes that one must offer to any stranger the right of
entry to a territory, home, or nation of which one is legitimately in possession.
-
With the concept of unconditional
hospitality, Derrida is not trying to offer a political program about how a pure
hospitality might be implemented; rather, he is trying to expose the presuppositions of conditional
hospitality and the series of concepts that it is based upon--such as one's proper residence, proper identity, and
proper cultural identity. For Derrida, there is an essential link between society or culture and
hospitality. In every society there is space allocated for those who are
invited and this enables the welcoming of the strangers who arrive. In
other words, conditional hospitality is what enables one's being at home.
There is no culture, no home, no nation or family without a door. It is
the opening of this door that functions as a
means of welcoming strangers. When the stranger, the Other, is welcomed on the condition
that he adjust to the chez soi, the hospitality that is offered is a conditional one, one of
visitation: the stranger is welcome only as long as he respects the order and rules of
the home, the nation or culture, and learns to speak the language. In contrast (but not in opposition) to conditional
hospitality is unconditional or pure hospitality: the pure welcoming of
the unexpected guest or anyone who arrives or visits, the hospitality of invitation. Conditional hospitality of
invitation is distinguished from the unconditional hospitality
of visitation by the fact that in the former, the master remains the
master, the host remains the host at home, and the guest remains an
invited guest. As an invited guest, one is expected not to alter the rule
and order of the home. Derrida imagines
the hospitality of visitation in order to distinguish it from the hospitality
of invitation where the stranger is not an invited guest, but one who
arrives unexpectedly, where the host opens the house without asking any
questions.
-
Derrida reminds us that the relation between the two forms of hospitality
has the same structure between law and justice (and let's remember that
according to Derrida justice is impossible); they are
heterogeneous but at the same time absolutely indissociable. These two
forms of hospitality refer to the legal and just forms of hospitality.
Like justice, unconditional hospitality is impossible as one cannot
deduce a rule from it. In other words, it is impossible to make it a rule
that nations, families, cultures, or governments should open their house
unconditionally to everyone and hence to turn it into an official policy.
Although it is impossible, Derrida nevertheless designates with the term
unconditional what hospitality should be in principle. Thus the concept
of conditional hospitality enables Derrida to conceive of
unconditional hospitality. As he puts it:
to think of this conditional hospitality one has to have in mind what
would be a pure hospitality to the messianic Other, the unexpected one
who just lands in my country and to whom I simply say: come and eat and
sleep and I won't even ask your name. ("A Discussion" 13)
If we have a concept of conditional hospitality, it's because we have
also the idea of a pure hospitality, of unconditional hospitality. (15)
- If unconditional or pure hospitality is impossible, then what is
the possibility of the politics of hospitality? Like the relation between
law and justice, where it is in the name of justice that one deconstructs
the law, it is in the name of unconditional hospitality that conditional
hospitality can be deconstructed. To tend to unconditional hospitality
one has to deconstruct and improve the laws on hospitality (such as
immigration laws), but these laws will never guarantee unconditional
hospitality as such. The relation between them will remain open and
irreducible. As Derrida notes, the law is perfectible and there is
progress to be performed on the law that will improve the conditions of
hospitality. The condition of the laws on immigration has to be improved
without claiming that unconditional law should become an official policy.
The very desire for unconditional hospitality is what regulates the
improvement of the laws of hospitality.
-
CONCLUSION
So how, then, can we rethink the forces of capitalist globalization and institutionalized multiculturalism,
which I suggested are working hand in hand, in light of the Derridian notion of unconditional hospitality? This essay has
not meant to imply that the operation of the forces of globalization are limited by the laws that regulate the welcoming of
immigrants or through institutionalizing multiculturalist respect and
tolerance. Globalization works on many fronts, and we need to be
vigilant: about the complicated links between globalization and the
workings of nation-states in the so-called Third World; about the novel ways in which
the rural is now accessed by global capital; about the interventions of the
World Trade Organization, the International Monetary Fund, and the World
Bank which impose as international law the laws of the
national economies of the global North; about the reinstitution of the
repressive powers of the nation-states in the Third World so as to enable
the smooth operation of global capital.[8] My analysis here engages with the question of
globalization in terms of its ideological and political presuppositions. The reason for my discussion of how liberal
multiculturalism functions as the ideal form of global capitalism and how it is conditioned by its
demands is twofold: first, to examine the hegemonic ideological form of
global capitalism as it relates to the ethnically and culturally Other; second, to challenge the idea that the valorization of
particular identities can be seen as a destabilizing counter-hegemonic
political force in the wake of the global abstraction of transnational
capitalism. I have suggested that Derrida's concept of conditional hospitality is a useful philosophical and theoretical
apparatus for deconstructing the ideology embedded in liberal multiculturalism.
-
But let me be clear: I do not mean to suggest that conditional hospitality should be dismantled, that the welcoming of
immigrants based on legal regulations should be done away with, or that unconditional hospitality should be substituted as the
official policy of the host nations. I do not recommend the concept of unconditional hospitality as a technical application of a
rule or norm. Unconditional hospitality is not to be regarded as the name
of a counter-political program against the global management of the
ethnically and culturally different. Nor is it a command that can
be conformed to or deviated from, as it cannot be treated as a rule or an injunction
that can organize the nature of the relation with immigrants.
Unconditional hospitality is neither a means of
determining judgment nor a rule of action. It is, rather, the condition of the possibility of the perfection and improvement of
conditional hospitality. Speaking of unconditional hospitality, Derrida
notes:
It's impossible as a rule, I cannot regularly organise unconditional
hospitality, and that's why, as a rule, I have a bad conscience, I cannot
have a good conscience because I know that I lock my door, and that a
number of people who would like to share my house, my apartment, my
nation, my money, my land and so on so forth. I say not as a rule, but sometimes, exceptionally, it may happen. I cannot
regulate, control or determine these moments, but it may happen, just as an act of forgiveness, some
forgiveness may happen, pure forgiveness may happen. I cannot make a
determinate, a determining judgement and say: 'this is pure forgiveness,'
or 'this is pure hospitality,' as an act of knowledge, there is no
adequate act of determining judgment. That's why the realm of action, of
practical reason, is absolutely heterogeneous to theory and theoretical
judgments here, but it may happen without even my knowing it, my being
conscious of it, or my having rules for its establishment. Unconditional
hospitality can't be an establishment, but it may happen as a miracle . . .
in an instant, not lasting more than an instant, it may happen. This is
the . . . possible happening of something impossible which makes us think
what hospitality, or forgiveness, or gift might be. ("A Discussion" 15-16)
- This "possible happening of something impossible" can be seen as the condition of a democratic
possibility. To use Derrida's formulation in The Other Heading:
Reflections on Today's Europe, this condition of democratic possibility is something "to be thought and to
come
[à venir]: not something that is certain to happen tomorrow, not the democracy (national or international, state or
trans-state) of the future, but a democracy that must have the
structure of a promise--and thus the memory of that which carries the
future, the to-come, here and now" (78). It is the introduction of
the notion of unconditionality into politics--or to put it in Balibar's term,
the politics of equaliberty, which is an all-or-nothing notion--that can
open the possibility of a democratic politics. As we saw earlier, Balibar argues that as an unconditional force, the demand
for equaliberty or the right to have rights cannot be relativized. The unconditional
nature of equaliberty, like the unconditionality of hospitality, is
distinct from this or that specific right guaranteed by law.
However neither equaliberty nor unconditional hospitality in themselves
are possible. But their impossibility should not be taken as the closure
of the possibility of democracy; on the contrary, it is the principle of
unconditionality which is the driving force behind the condition of
possibility of a democratic opening and, with it, a revision in law.
-
At this point, it might be useful to situate the demand for equaliberty
and the ethics of hospitality in the context of contemporary global
capitalism, as my aim is not to theorize them as pure, atemporal and
context-independent forces ultimately separated from forces of economy
and politics.
-
From the point of view of politics proper, globalization can be characterized as a contradictory process: on the one hand,
the very processes of globalization produce the demand for equaliberty. The globalization of production and other market
forces necessarily create the conditions for the welcoming of immigrants as well as the granting of certain rights. These
very same groups, as a consequence of the production of new political and ideological needs, make claims that may be against
the interests of global capitalism. On the other hand, however, globalization is a law-governed process, and
institutionalizing forces such as the International Monetary Fund and the World Bank absorb the demand for equaliberty
through the mechanism of the law. Thus, the ideal of the right to have rights or the demand for equaliberty is necessarily
compromised as it becomes articulated within global capitalism. And it is in this regard that Negri's analysis becomes
useful for understanding the constriction of politics proper through constitutional means. Such institutionalization
coincides with the direction global capitalism has taken. Demands for equaliberty are always compromised, always diluted and
contained by their expression within lawful and institutionalized processes.
-
In the face of this compromise, where can we situate the possibility of a democratic politics? In the face of this
containment of the politics for equaliberty in global capitalism, must we forfeit the desire for unconditional hospitality?
In a word: no. But the task is to rethink the very force of the demand for equaliberty not in terms of its full
realization--as this would imply a total transcendence of global capitalism, which at the very least will not come any time
soon--but precisely in terms of its inevitable containment or dilution by global forces. For unconditional hospitality or
the demand for equaliberty is not exhausted by or reduced to the current historical context of the granting of conditional
and legal rights. Neither is its full realization contingent upon the transcendence of the capitalist world system.
Instead, unconditional hospitality has to be understood as immanent to the present--"the possible happening of something
impossible"-- demanding, in the present, the immediate transformation of the present conditions of hospitality.
Department of Sociology
Middle East Technical University
meyda@metu.edu.tr
COPYRIGHT (c) 2003 Meyda Yegenoglu. READERS MAY USE
PORTIONS OF THIS WORK IN ACCORDANCE WITH THE FAIR USE PROVISIONS OF U.S.
COPYRIGHT LAW. IN ADDITION, SUBSCRIBERS AND MEMBERS OF SUBSCRIBED
INSTITUTIONS MAY
USE THE ENTIRE WORK FOR ANY INTERNAL NONCOMMERCIAL PURPOSE BUT, OTHER THAN
ONE COPY SENT BY EMAIL, PRINT OR FAX TO ONE PERSON AT ANOTHER LOCATION FOR
THAT INDIVIDUAL'S PERSONAL USE, DISTRIBUTION OF THIS ARTICLE OUTSIDE OF A
SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION FROM EITHER THE
AUTHOR OR THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS IS EXPRESSLY FORBIDDEN.
THIS ARTICLE AND OTHER CONTENTS OF THIS ISSUE ARE
AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE UNTIL RELEASE OF THE NEXT ISSUE. A
TEXT-ONLY ARCHIVE OF THE JOURNAL IS ALSO AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE.
FOR FULL HYPERTEXT ACCESS TO BACK ISSUES, SEARCH UTILITIES, AND OTHER
VALUABLE FEATURES, YOU OR YOUR INSTITUTION MAY SUBSCRIBE TO
PROJECT MUSE, THE
ON-LINE JOURNALS PROJECT OF THE
JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS.
Notes
I am grateful to Kenneth Bar and Mahmut Mutman for their close reading of
the essay and for providing suggestions which helped me to clarify the
arguments developed here.
1. The
distinction Etienne Balibar
makes between three forms of universality, namely "real universality,"
"fictitious universality," and "ideal universality," is a very
useful one to rethink the difference between the nature of the
universality that globalization implies (which Balibar calls "real
universality"). He differentiates it from "ideal universality." The
latter refers to a subversive element and is intrinsically linked
with the notion of insurrection and rebellion in the name of
freedom and equality. See "Ambiguous
Universality."
2. Balibar designates this "new world order" with the
term "real universality." See "Ambiguous Universality."
3. For Zizek the term "politics
proper" "always involves a kind of short circuit between the universal
and the particular; it involves a paradox of a singular that appears as a
stand-in for the universal . . . . This singulier universel is a
group that . . . not only demands to be heard on equal footing with the
ruling oligarchy or aristocracy . . . but, even more, presents itself as the
immediate embodiment of society as such, in its universality,
against the particular power interests of aristocracy and oligarchy" ("A
Leftist Plea" 988-89).
4. Derrida notes that the German word for hospitality
is about the stranger's right, upon arrival to the domain of another, to
be treated not as an enemy. Hence hospitality is in opposition precisely
to opposition itself, that is, to hostility. The guest, who is hosted as
the opposite of the one who is treated as an enemy, is a stranger who is
treated as an ally.
5. Kant adds the word
Wirbarkeit as synonymous to the word hospitality. The word
Wirt(in), Derrida writes, refers to host and guest, the host who
accepts the guest. Derrida notes that the word Gastgeber refers
to the owner (proprietor) of a hotel or restaurant. Like
Gastlich, Wirtlich, also means the one who hosts or
accepts. Wirt, Wirtschaft thus refers to the domain of economy,
the governing of home.
6. By this way, hospitality becomes the threshold
itself. For hospitality to exist there has to be a door. But when there
are doors that means there is no (unconditional) welcoming as this implies
that someone has the key for the door and thus controls the condition of
hospitality.
7. As it will become clear in
the following pages, it is legitimate to discuss the relation between
these two as they have the same structure.
8. For a fuller discussion of these issues see Yegenoglu and Mutman.
Works Cited
Agamben, Giorgio. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare
Life. Trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1998.
Appadurai, Arjun. "Disjuncture and Difference in the Global Cultural
Economy." Global Culture: Nationalism, Globalization and
Modernity. Ed. Mike Featherstone. London: Sage, 1990: 295-310.
Balibar, Etienne. "Ambiguous Universality." differences
7.1 (1995): 48-74.
Bennett, David. "Introduction." Multicultural States: Rethinking
Difference and Identity. Ed. David Bennett. London:
Routledge, 1998: 1-25.
Derrida, Jacques. Adieu to Emmanuel Levinas. Ed. Werner Hamacher and David E.
Wellbery. Trans. Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael Naas. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1999.
-----. "A Discussion with Jacques Derrida." Theory and Event 5.1: 2001. Available: <http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/theory_and-event?v005/5.1
derrida.html>.
-----. "Force of Law: The 'Mystical Foundation of Authority.'"
Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice. Ed.
Drucilla Cornell et. al. New York: Routledge, 1992: 3-67.
-----. "Hospitality." Angelaki 5.3 (Dec. 2000):
3-18.
-----. The Other Heading: Reflections on Today's Europe.
Trans. Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael B. Naas. Bloomington, IN:
Indiana UP, 1992.
Dirlik, Arif. "The Global in the Local." Global/Local: Cultural
Production and the Transnational Imaginary. Ed. Rob Wilson and Wimal Dissanayake. Durham, NC: Duke UP, 1996: 21-45.
Hall, Stuart. "The Local and the Global: Globalization and Ethnicity."
Culture, Globalization and the World-System: Contemporary Conditions for the Representation of Identity. Ed.
Anthony D. King. Binghamton, NY: Macmillan, 1991: 19-39.
Hannerz, Ulf. "Cosmopolitans and Locals in World Culture." Global
Culture: Nationalism, Globalization and Modernity. Ed. Mike
Featherstone. London: Sage, 1990: 237-251.
Laclau, Ernesto. "Subject of Politics, Politics of the Subject."
differences 7.1 (1995): 146-164.
Lloyd, David, "Race under Representation." Oxford Literary
Review 13.1-2 (1991): 62-94.
Negri, Antonio. Insurgencies: Constituent Power and the Modern
State. Trans. Maurizia Boscagli. Minneapolis, MN: U of Minnesota P,
1999.
Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty. A Critique of Postcolonial Reason:
Toward a History of the Vanishing Present. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard UP, 1999.
Yegenoglu, Meyda. Colonial Fantasies: Towards a Feminist Reading
of Orientalism. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1998.
Yegenoglu, Meyda, and Mahmut Mutman. "Mapping the Present: Interview
with Gayatri Spivak." New Formations 45 (Winter
2001-02): 9-23.
Zizek, Slavoj. "A Leftist Plea for 'Eurocentrism.'" Critical
Inquiry 24. 4 (Summer 1998): 988-1009.
-----. "Multiculturalism, Or, the Cultural Logic of Multinational
Capitalism." New Left Review. 225 September/October
(1997): 28-51.
|