Review of:
Tom Cohen, et al., eds., Material Events: Paul de Man and the
Afterlife of Theory. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2001.
- As we confront the triumph of USA-centrism ("institutionalize
diversity locally, maximize profit globally"), to trace our historicity,
defined by punctual "material events," we need to contest what Paul de Man
calls "aesthetic ideology." So argues Material Events,
co-edited by Tom Cohen, Barbara Cohen, J. Hillis Miller, and Andrzej
Warminski. Material Events includes path-breaking essays that
examine Cézanne's paintings, Hitchcock's films, and Descarte's
notions about the body. With contributions by Jacques Derrida, Judith
Butler, Arkady Plotnitsky, and Barbara Johnson, this volume is one of the
most important responses to Paul de Man's work, especially the posthumous
Aesthetic Ideology, yet published.[1]
- Material Events will upset academics
skeptical of "theory" in general and of "deconstruction" in particular
(however, this collection reminds us why "theory" is not the best term to
define "deconstruction"). But Material Events, which
examines the relevance of de Man's arguments to psychoanalysis, political
science, and law, should not only irritate academics impatient to
conserve traditions and the boundaries between them. Many, but not all,
instructors and researchers who want to be effectively progressive may be
disturbed by the editors' claim that aesthetic ideology dominates the
contemporary university.
- de Man's study of aesthetic ideology interrogates a key
procedure of higher education: the aestheticization of singularities to
render them as knowable, exchangeable representatives. In this regard,
the university's pursuit of knowledge may truly participate in an
exercise of Eurocentric, now actually USA-centric, power. Indeed, the
example of "diversity" helps to define the import of Material
Events. de Man did not address what the university now calls
"multiculturalism." But this term specifies the stakes of de Man's last
essays, especially as explicated by and expanded upon in this new
collection: textual "material events" breach the aesthetic erasures of
otherness that contemporary academic institutions (and their governmental
and transnational corporate sponsors) thrive on while asserting their
commitment to "diversity."
- The university's academic mission is a cognitive one: to
gain rational knowledge and to teach that knowledge to students. This
mission cannot avoid being political, and thus ideological, especially when
the university attempts to know the "diverse." By aestheticizing
"diversity" to institutionalize a knowledge of "cultures," the university
may be perpetuating rather than contesting one of higher education's most
longstanding and pronouncedly ideological projects: that of managing or
containing socioeconomic conflicts by instituting "culture" as a
function of what Friedrich Schiller called "aesthetic education." Samuel
Taylor Coleridge's On the Constitution of the Church and
State articulated the version of this project that was taken up by
John Stuart Mill and Matthew Arnold.[2]
- Material Events suggests that a claim de Man
made in 1983 is now even more valid: "the standards... and the values by
means of which we teach... are more than ever and profoundly Schillerian"
(Aesthetic 142). In the sentences about "diversity" that
colleges and universities include in their mission statements, one often
finds an unintentional paraphrase of Schiller, Coleridge, Mill, and/or
Arnold on the relations between culture, education, and the state. The
likelihood, de Man might argue, that such documents' authors have never
read Schiller or Coleridge on the relations between the aesthetic and the
workings of state power only underlines the pervasiveness of aesthetic
ideology.
- At issue is such ideology's impact on various studies.
Material Events asks: Can de Man's work on the aesthetic help
academics focused on feminist, ethnic, cultural, or literary studies to
contest ideology and to access the materiality of history? Can de Man aid
us in becoming better readers of Marx, Gramsci, or Althusser? The
contributions relevant to this last question are those by J. Hillis
Miller, Ernesto Laclau, Michael Sprinker, and Andrzej Warminski. Though
de Man has often been regraded as a figure of the right, and even his
defenders have not claimed a place for him in the Western Marxist
tradition, Miller argues that "a deep kinship exists between de Man's
work and Marx's thought in The German Ideology" (186). Laclau
discusses de Man on tropes to examine the political strategies of
hegemony. Sprinker explores the parallels and disjunctions between de Man
and Althusser on ideology. Warminski elaborates de Man's definition of
"material events" to suggest how de Man's analysis of aesthetic ideology
"is 'truer' to Marx's own procedures" than most contemporary attempts at
ideology critique (22).
- According to Miller's "Paul de Man as Allergen," academia
is allergic to de Man's arguments about materiality because they dispute
"basic ideological assumptions" that both academics and the university
itself "need to get on with [their] work" (185). The university needs to
assume (1) that what it engages is available as a presence or a phenomenon
that academic discourses can re-present and so know, and (2) that such
engagement is politically neutral. For de Man, these assumptions involve
a reaction, Miller says an allergic one, to a radically nonphenomenal
materiality by which alterity impinges on the university while evading the
university's cognitive grasp. Such materiality affects thought yet exceeds
any representation thought posits.
- The crux of Material Events is de Man's
differentiation between the phenomenality of phenomena known, the artifact
of a cognitive system of tropes that induces reference's aberrant
confusion with phenomenalism, and (the) materiality (of inscription).
Miller explains that for de Man, outrageously enough, materiality is
nothing phenomenal: no intuition of materiality is possible (yet
materiality is seen--more on this below). de Man's precisely
"counterintuitive concept" of materiality, writes Miller, "is not really a
concept" (185). Materiality does not defeat intuition in Platonic fashion,
by being an idea inaccessible to the senses. For Platonism, ideas
facilitate intuition by ordering the sensible into intelligibility. Any
given sensible table is intelligible as such because it participates in
the non-sensible idea "table." Traditionally, matters of knowledge are
phenomenal. Neither Platonically sensible nor intelligible, materiality is
irreducible to a matter of knowledge. Plotnitsky argues that, for de Man,
the term "materiality" refers to a singularity that utterly evades all
theorization, rule making, or "classical" knowledge production.
- Materiality's nonphenomenality relates to a potently
allergenic de Manean definition: "What we call ideology is precisely the
confusion of linguistic with natural reality, of reference with
phenomenalism" (de Man, Resistance 11). In aesthetic
ideology, what is called a referent's phenomenality is an artifact of the
apparatus that apprehends and equates a given referent with another to
produce a set of what are then cognized as mutually substitutable
entities, whether the apparatus is an anthropological survey or a formula
in geometry. Knowledge production depends on such aestheticization: the
equation of singularities as substitutable phenomena that may be
conceived of as identical. Where such aestheticization, the pursuit of
knowledge, and the reproduction of institutions converge, ideology exists.
- Are we awash in aesthetic ideology? Say that, to track
the institutionalization of "diversity," a United States university or
college gathers statistics numerically defining professors as falling
into various categories. To produce this knowledge, the university or
college must equate and so homogenize, that is, aestheticize,
singularities: one person plus another equals two who fall into this or
that category only when we know both as mutually substitutable phenomena.
So, for example, we may view Japanese Americans as interchangeable when
we confuse a reference for a phenomenal intuition: "When I see Professors
Y and Z, I am seeing two interchangeable examples of an identical
phenomenon." The interchangeability, confused for an instance of
phenomenalism, is actually an artifact of language's referential
function, here a certain language of "diversity" that refers to one
person as substituting for (as re-presenting) another. Resorting to this
language, we gain important knowledge: How many Japanese Americans has
the institution hired? But this language's referential artifact, confused
for a phenomenon, yields an aesthetic ideology that fashions peoples by
whitening out singular traces of alterity among people. This whitening
out is a kind of violence.
- Material Events confronts the complex,
sometimes grave, consequences of knowledge production's inseparability
from ideology. By instituting the substitution of whole (nation, culture,
gender, ethnicity) and part (member), aestheticization posits the
homogenizing idea that a nation's, culture's, gender's, or ethnicity's
members represent each other. The dependence of this idea, and so of the
knowledge organized by it, on a trope, in this case synecdoche, defines
what de Man calls "tropological system[s] of cognition"
(Aesthetic 133). But the aestheticization that yields this
idea also structures and produces the ideology that facilitates
prejudices: "Those _____, they are all alike; they all _____." Fill in
the blanks as your prejudice dictates: aesthetic ideology structures
racism, but also anti-Semitism, sexism, and homophobia. The prejudices
that aesthetic ideology houses depend on the aberrant confusion of
referentiality with phenomenality even when the "phenomenon" in question
is a moral abstraction: "When you look at _____, you see evil; when you
look at _____, you see good." Prejudice's template, aesthetic ideology,
results not only in what multiculturalists call "stereotypes," but also
in acts of violence.
- Defining the singular other we are about to encounter as
a representative _____, we exercise knowledge that is tied to
aestheticization. Simultaneously, our thoughts and actions may be
enclosed by an ideology that can control our relations with him or her.
The knowledge and the ideology can reinforce each other to the point
where little distinction remains. The violence that is and results from
racial profiling in police work exemplifies this dynamic. Here the
definition of the "typical" criminal's "profile" virtually merges with an
ideology, in this case racial ideology. And ideology can facilitate
racist violence in subtler ways. "Ideology is always mimetic ideology,"
and Material Events suggests that aesthetic ideology
currently pervades various mise en scènes of
representation (xii). Think of the staging of singular others as
"representative" members of ethnic or "racial" minorities at last
summer's Republican and Democratic national conventions, and remember
that both parties diligently pursue policies that are quite detrimental
to and violent toward those referred to as working-class Latinos and
African Americans. Some of these policies violently enact racist
inequality. The "war on drugs," which fuels racial profiling and results
in dramatic racist inequalities in arrest and incarceration rates, is an
example.
- But, de Man reminds us, "the political power of the
aesthetic, the measure of its impact on reality, necessarily travels by
ways of its didactic manifestations. The politics of the aesthetic state
are the politics of education" (Rhetoric 273). Pursuing
"diversity," higher education would institutionalize literature as
cultures' aesthetic representation. Many educators teach literature to
help students know themselves and others as representatives of cultures or
groups, which are thus assumed merely to be presences available to
consciousness for representation. The related assumption is that reading a
literary work yields cognition of a representative _____ that allows
students to know themselves and others as such _____. Again, literature
professors inherit these assumptions about pedagogy from influential
eighteenth- and nineteenth-century accounts of how aesthetic education
helps the liberal state to smooth over socioeconomic conflicts. Perhaps
especially in what we still call "English" or "Literature" departments,
these assumptions lead professors and students, however radical their
intentions, to reinforce ideologies that tend to reproduce existing
relations of production.
- Material Events leads us to ask whether
contemporary modes of research and pedagogy remain captured by aesthetic
ideology and so are finally unable effectively to contest, for example,
racism, sexism, or homophobia. In the collection's introduction, "A
'Materiality without Matter'?," the editors' most uncompromising concern
emerges: contemporary "aesthetic education" may assist the very
injustices academics and their institutions often claim to resist: "The
strategies of historicism, of identity politics, or cultural studies" too
often participate in an ideological "relapse" by imposing "a model of
reference... upon the same conceptual space whose impulse is to fabricate
an organizing ground or immediacy (the subject, experience, history) that
effaces the problematic of inscription" (xi).
- The editors argue that in the contemporary academy, but
also more generally, we find in place "an aesthetico-political regime, an
occlusion of the order of inscription... in favor of tropes guarding the
claims of human immediacy and perception" (xii). This emphasis on higher
education as ideology's site of reproduction certainly accords with
Althusser's claim that, while the church was feudalism's central
"ideological state apparatus," the dominant ideological state apparatus
"in mature capitalist social formations... is the educational
ideological apparatus" (152). Miller and
Sprinker assert that de Man's claims about aesthetic ideology parallel
Althusser's statement that "Ideology is a 'Representation' of the
Imaginary Relationship of Individuals to their Real Conditions of
Existence" (162).
- But Sprinker finds de Man somewhat Stalinist: de Man's
"strict insistence on historical necessity, on, as it were, the iron laws
of the dialectic (to translate de Manian strictures into a familiar
idiom), is anything but Marxist" (42). Sprinker judges that, for de Man,
history "is governed by structures as invariant and ineluctable as those
that command linguistic tropes" (41). Both Plotnitsky and Miller reject
this characterization, arguing that de Manean
material events are unknowable, especially in terms of "iron laws." In
contrast to Sprinker, who finds de Man to associate historicity with
tropes, Miller writes that, for de Man, "the materiality of history,
properly speaking, is the result of acts of power that are punctual and
momentary, since they are atemporal, noncognitive and noncognizable
performative utterances" (188).
- So how does de Man link tropes, material events, and
performatives? Are tropes or are performatives material events? As Miller
specifies, de Man argues that history, as a material event, occurs in the
"shift from cognitive to efficaciously performative discourse" (188).
Here a quote from the transcription of de Man's lecture "Kant and
Schiller" is in order:
The linguistic model for [the material event is not]... the performative
in itself--because the performative in itself exists independently of tropes
and exists independently of a critical examination or of an
epistemological examination of tropes--but the transition, the passage
from a conception of language as a [cognitive tropological] system... to
another conception of language in which language is no longer
cognitive but in which language is performative.
(Aesthetic 132)
In "'As the poets do it': On the Material Sublime," Warminski cites the
above sentences to sanction his counsel against a "misreading of
de Man" that results in "a certain inflation and overvaluation of the
performative" (25). The material event is neither a
cognitive trope nor a performative utterance but the passage from one to
the other. The passage from trope to performative "occurs always, and can
only occur, by ways of an epistemological critique of trope" (de Man,
Aesthetic 133). Lenin, but possibly not Althusser, might
have balked at taking the "epistemological critique of trope" as an
answer to the question: What is to be done? Yet Material
Events implies that racist, sexist, homophobic, and anti-Semitic
instances of aesthetic ideology may be best resisted by means of just such a
"critical-linguistic analysis" (de Man, Resistance 121).
- However, Warminski cautions us, this "critical-linguistic
analysis" should not be mistaken for, to use de Man's phrase, "what
generally passes as 'critique of ideology'" (de Man,
Resistance 121). Pedagogies that would "demystify" or
"unmask" stereotypes by uncovering what the stereotyped really are like
"substitute one trope for another" and are thus condemned "to remain very
much within (and hence to confirm) the tropological
system" they aim to criticize (Warminski, "Allegories" 11).
- Warminski is not suggesting that we are unable to
develop better knowledge. The argument is that, say, Toni Morrison's
Beloved, if it contests ideology, does so not primarily by
giving readers better knowledge, a more or "politically" correct
re-presentation, but by enacting a passage from a cognitive to a
performative discourse. A material event, this passage would
disarticulate tropological systems that, referring to African Americans,
posit an object of knowledge ("race") and an ideology ("racism").
- de Man argues that a crucial instance of disarticulation
marks Kant's Critique of Judgment. Any reader who has
struggled with de Man's crucial essay in Aesthetic Ideology,
"Phenomenality and Materiality in Kant," will welcome Warminski's essay on
the "material" sublime. Warminski patiently explicates de Man's complex
argument that the Kantian sublime's moments are structured by linguistic
principles. The transition from the tropological system Kant calls the
"mathematical" sublime to the performative Kant calls the "dynamic"
sublime happens by way of a "material" sublime. de Man reads this
"material" sublime in Kant's description of an ocean vaulted by sky. de
Man states that in this scene "no mind is involved.... This vision is
purely material, devoid of any reflexive or intellectual complication[;]
it is also purely formal, devoid of any semantic depth"
(Aesthetic 82-3). This "material vision" is nonphenomenal in
part because no intentional structure of consciousness is at work. In
Althusserian terms, the "material" sublime countenances no interpellative
effects. And this vision allegorizes the materiality of language
unavailable to phenomenalization. Finally, the "material sublime" is an
event that constitutes a "deep, perhaps fatal, break or discontinuity" in
Kant's project to articulate "transcendental" with "metaphysical"
principles, or, in de Man's terms, the "critical" with the "ideological"
(Aesthetic 79, 70-73). For de Man, Warminski explains, this
break disarticulates the "critical [Kantian] philosophy itself" while
being a result of that philosophy's very rigor (17).
- For all de Man's focus on Kant, we would be mistaken if
we were to think that "material events" are merely occurrences in
"intellectual" or "literary" history. Miller dispels this
misunderstanding. The shift from cognitive to performative language in
Kant's Critique of Judgment is a material event. de Man finds
Schiller's reception of that text to attempt a recuperation of that event
"by reinscribing it in the cognition of tropes," and he argues that this
"is itself a tropological, cognitive, and not a historical move"
(Aesthetic 134). But (historians prepare to be irritated),
for de Man, the disarticulation that the Critique of Judgment
enacts should be thought of as a historical event, much as we might think
of the storming of the Bastille as a historical event. In de Man's terms,
the storming of the Bastille itself resulted from a "prior" historical
event. In Paris on 14 July 1789 the cry "To the Bastille!" was a
felicitous speech act, but that performative was not in itself the
precipitating historical event. The material event was a kind of shift or
transition--a radically nontemporal, nonspatial, nonphenomenal
passage--by means of which that performative emerged from the
disarticulation of a system of tropes that posited feudal ideology.
- Aestheticization ties knowledge to ideology. But,
attempting to know an unknowable materiality, we dismantle knowledge's
authority. In discussing de Man's "authority without authority," Miller
writes:
This authority... undoes all grounds for speaking with authority. How can
one speak intelligibly on the grounds of the unintelligible? At the
limit, and indeed all along the way, de Man's writings are allergenic
because they pass on to the reader an allergen, an otherness, with which
they have been infected and that is quite other to the calm, implacable,
rational, maddeningly difficult to refute, rigor of de Man's
argumentation. Or rather, the latter turns out to be the same as the
former, reason to be other to itself. (200-201)
When we find "reason to be other to itself," we may be able, not to
escape, but to resist "the reproduction... of aesthetic ideology" (183).
This is one of many lessons Material Events teaches, and
they are worth learning.
English and Foreign Languages Division
Pasadena City College
rsoventile@paccd.cc.ca.us
COPYRIGHT (c) 2001 BY ROBERT S. OVENTILE.
READERS MAY USE PORTIONS
OF THIS WORK IN ACCORDANCE WITH THE FAIR USE PROVISIONS OF U.S. COPYRIGHT
LAW. IN ADDITION, SUBSCRIBERS AND MEMBERS OF SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTIONS MAY
USE THE ENTIRE WORK FOR ANY INTERNAL NONCOMMERCIAL PURPOSE BUT, OTHER THAN
ONE COPY SENT BY EMAIL, PRINT OR FAX TO ONE PERSON AT ANOTHER LOCATION FOR
THAT INDIVIDUAL'S PERSONAL USE, DISTRIBUTION OF THIS ARTICLE OUTSIDE OF A
SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION FROM EITHER THE
AUTHOR OR THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS IS EXPRESSLY FORBIDDEN.
THIS ARTICLE AND OTHER CONTENTS OF THIS ISSUE ARE
AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE UNTIL RELEASE OF THE NEXT ISSUE. A
TEXT-ONLY ARCHIVE OF THE JOURNAL IS ALSO AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE. FOR
FULL HYPERTEXT ACCESS TO BACK ISSUES, SEARCH UTILITIES, AND OTHER VALUABLE
FEATURES, YOU OR YOUR INSTITUTION MAY SUBSCRIBE TO
PROJECT MUSE, THE
ON-LINE JOURNALS PROJECT OF THE JOHNS
HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS.
Notes
1. See also: Jacques Derrida,
Memoires for Paul de Man, trans. Cecile Lindsay, et al.,
rev. ed. (New York: Columbia UP, 1989); Rodolphe Gasché, The
Wild Card of Reading: On Paul de Man (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP,
1998); Christopher Norris, Paul de Man: Deconstruction and the
Critique of Aesthetic Ideology (New York: Routledge, 1988); and
Lindsay Waters and Wlad Godzich, eds., Reading de Man
Reading (Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1989).
2. See David Lloyd and Paul Thomas,
Culture and the State (New York: Routledge, 1998).
Works Cited
Althusser, Louis. Lenin and Philosophy and Other
Essays. Trans. Ben Brewster. New York: Monthly Review, 1971.
de Man, Paul. Aesthetic Ideology. Ed. Andrzej
Warminski. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1996.
---. The Resistance to Theory. Fwd. Wlad Godzich.
Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1986.
---. The Rhetoric of Romanticism. New York: Columbia UP,
1984.
Warminski, Andrzej. "Allegories of Reference."
Introduction. Aesthetic Ideology. By Paul de Man.
Ed. Andrzej Warminski. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P,
1996. 1-33.
|