Review of: Simon Critchley, Ethics, Politics, Subjectivity:
Essays on Derrida, Levinas, and Contemporary French Thought. London: Verso,
1999.
-
In his latest collection of essays, Ethics, Politics,
Subjectivity, Simon Critchley extends and modifies the
discussion of deconstruction and ethics that he put forward in his
earlier book, The Ethics of Deconstruction. Like
that earlier work, Ethics, Politics,
Subjectivity examines the nature--or rather, the
possibility--of ethics and politics after (or during) deconstruction
in relation primarily to the work of Jacques Derrida and Emmanuel
Levinas. In contrast to his position in the earlier book, however,
Critchley's reading or assessment of Levinasian ethics in
Ethics, Politics, Subjectivity is, as he puts it, "a
critical reconstruction" (ix). Specifically, he extends, deepens,
and modifies his arguments about the "persuasive force" of
Levinasian ethics in regard to deconstruction. One way of reading
Ethics, Politics, Subjectivity (a way that Critchley
seems to encourage in the preface) is to see the culmination of this
consideration of the subject in his affirmation of the political
possibilities of deconstruction (chapter 12).
-
However, because Critchley investigates subjectivity outside the issues of
deconstruction and politics, it would be unfortunate to read his essays strictly
in terms of such a culmination. For instance, his discussions of subjectivity,
ethics, sublimation, and art in "The Original Traumatism: Levinas and
Psychoanalysis" (chapter 8) and in "Das Ding: Lacan and Levinas" (chapter 9) provide a reconstruction (or an additional reading) of Levinasian
ethics outside of the question of politics. In addition, and more importantly in
regard to the aims of this review, Critchley's careful treatment of subjectivity
distinguishes Ethics, Politics, Subjectivity from a number of
"postmodern" treatises on the subject. It is, I think, this carefulness (which
is enacted as much as it is expressed) that makes the strongest case for the
political possibilities of deconstruction.
-
When I say "postmodern" treatises on the subject, I am referring to the work in a
number of fields (e.g., literary theory, rhetoric and composition, and
cultural
studies) that takes for granted the dissolution of the humanist subject, declares
its epiphenomenal status, and then celebrates postmodernism's victory over the
Enlightenment, or homo rhetoricus's victory over homo seriosus,
often taking for granted the ascendancy of ethics over politics. Often these
arguments contend that politics are based on the assumption that humans are free
to deliberate on issues, to express opinions, and take collective action.
However, since the means of reaching consensus are always already predetermined
by hegemonic, capitalistic forces, the political endeavor--as traditionally
understood, for example, in terms of various ideologies of the Enlightenment--is
a doomed endeavor. It is on this basis that some scholars attempt to distinguish
the ethical from the political, and in doing so advocate new modes of
subjectivity or post-subjectivity--for instance, following Deleuze and Guattari,
the schizophrenic or rhizomatic modes; following Baudrillard, the seductive mode;
and following Gorgias, the sophistic mode. In fact, it is the question of
subjectivity that seems to drive these arguments; that is, the exigency for their
discussion of ethics and politics is the dissolution of the humanist subject.
While I do not want to imply that such arguments are simplistic or unwarranted
(since Quintilian's "good man speaking well" is indeed alive and thriving), I do
want to suggest that this exigency potentially leads to totalizing conceptions of
the subject, or, conversely, of the dissolution of the subject, as well as
problematic conceptions of the relationship between ethics and politics.
- It is precisely this exigency that Critchley problematizes in his
third chapter, "Post-Deconstructive Subjectivity." By turning Heidegger's critique
of Husserl (and Descartes) back onto Heidegger, Critchley explores the possibility
of a conception of the subject outside of metaphysics. Specifically, he argues
that the very grounds that distinguish Dasein from a contemplative
subject (the openness to the call to Being) can be read metaphysically, which is
to say that they can be read as modes of authentic selfhood. "It is
Dasein," he claims, "who calls itself in the phenomenon of conscience, .
. . and the voice of the friend that calls Dasein to its most authentic
ability to be . . . is a voice that Dasein carries within it" (58).
Based on this Heideggerian argument, then, there is no subject outside of
metaphysics. From this position, Critchley questions the history and the
presuppositions entailed in the idea of a post-metaphysical subject. Among these
presuppositions, he contends, is the idea that we have achieved an "epochal break
in the continuum of history." "For reasons that one might call 'classically'
Derridian," he continues, "all ideas of exceeding the metaphysical closure should
make us highly suspicious, and the seductive illusions of 'overcoming',
'exceeding', 'transgressing', 'breaking through', and 'stepping beyond' are a
series of tropes that demand careful and persistent deconstruction" (59).
-
Indeed, Critchley finds problematic the very argument that there was a
metaphysical res cogitans, a subject of representation, in
Descartes's work--a paradigmatic case and a key starting point in
the history of the idea of the unified subject. It is because this
unified self has been retrospectively projected onto all conceptions
of the subject since Descartes that Critchley sees the history of
modern philosophy as (in part) "a series of caricatures or cartoon
versions of the history of metaphysics, a series of narratives based
upon a greater or lesser misreading of the philosophical tradition"
(60). "Has there ever existed a unified conscious subject, a
watertight Cartesian ego?" he asks (59).
-
Although Critchley's response to the question is "no," he does not advocate a
pre-Heideggerian conception of the subject, the subject that is outside
metaphysics. In other words, Critchley argues, following John Llewelyn, that we
must seek a conception of the subject that tries to avoid the metaphysics of
subjectivity without falling into the metaphysical denial of metaphysics (73).
Critchley finds this attempt in Levinasian ethics--in its nuanced account of
metaphysics, subjectivity, and the relation between subjective experience and the
other. For Critchley, what's most important in Levinasian ethics is the shift
from intentionality to sensing, which is to say the shift from representation to
enjoyment. As Critchley puts it, "Levinas's work offers a
material phenomenology of subjective life. . . . The self-conscious,
autonomous subject of intentionality is
reduced to a living subject that is subject to the conditions of its existence"
(63). It is because of this sentience that the I is capable of being called into
question by the other. The I, in fact, is more accurately a me in
Levinasian ethics and subjectivity in that the subject is subject precisely
because it (its freedom) undergoes the call of the other. According to
Critchley, then, the (post-) Levinasian conception of the subject does not react
conservatively to the poststructuralist or antihumanist critique of
subjectivity by trying to rehabilitate the free, autarchic ego (70). Rather, it
needs these discourses in order to conceive of the subject as non-identical,
overflowed, and dependent on that which is it incapable of knowing. "Levinasian
ethics," Critchley contends, "is a humanism, but it is a humanism of the other
human being" (67).
-
In the final section of the essay, Critchley argues that the Levinasian
conception of the sentient, ethical subject is very close to the
kind of postdeconstructive subjectivity sought by Derrida.
According to Critchley, Derrida has called for a "new determination
of the 'subject' in terms of responsibility, of an affirmative
openness to the other prior to questioning" (71). While Critchley
does not suggest that Derrida is referring only or directly to
Levinas's conception of the subject, he does stress the consonance
between the subject that is formed by non-comprehensible experience
of the other and the postdeconstructive subject alluded to by
Derrida. He claims, for instance, that the determination of the
Levinasian subject "takes place precisely in the space cleared by
the anti-humanist and post-structuralist deconstruction of
subjectivity" (73). What's more, according to Critchley, is that
Levinas offers a metaphysical account of ethics and the subject
while simultaneously displacing and transforming metaphysical
language. For example, in Levinas's work, "ethics" is transformed
to mean "a sensible responsibility to the singular other";
"metaphysics" becomes "the movement of positive desire tending
towards infinite alterity," and "subjectivity" is "pre-conscious,
non-identical sentient subjection to the other" (75). As a result
of these conceptual shifts, he argues, the Levinasian subject avoids
predeconstructive metaphysics, or intentionality, without
attempting a Heideggerian denial of metaphysics.
-
In "Deconstruction and Pragmatism: Is Derrida a Private Ironist or a Public
Liberal?" (chapter 4), Critchley moves away from a direct
discussion of subjectivity in order to consider the political/public
potentialities of deconstruction. Specifically, by taking issue
with Richard Rorty's classification of Derrida as a private ironist,
he articulates a connection between Rorty's conceptions of the
public and the liberal ironist and Derrida's conception of justice
and thereby argues for the public value of deconstruction.
Critchley begins this argument by problematizing the grounds upon
which Rorty's classification of Derrida depends. For Rorty,
Critchley explains, Derrida is a private ironist because his
projects have become individualized projects of self-creation or
self-overcoming--they have become non-argumentative, oracular
discourses that do not address the problems of social justice (95).
In Critchley's view, Rorty's claim (his developmental thesis)
depends upon a reductive periodization of Derrida's work, as well as
a foundational conception of argument or public discourse.
Moreover, Critchley argues that what Rorty has observed is not a
change in the public significance of Derrida's work, but rather a
shift "from a constative form of theorizing to a performative mode
of writing, or, in other terms, from meta-language to language"
(96).
-
What ultimately problematizes Rorty's classification, however, is the connection
that Critchley sees between Rorty's definition of public liberal and
Derrida's conception of justice. For Rorty, the public is defined
as that which is concerned with "'the suffering of other human
beings', with the attempt to minimize cruelty and work for social
justice" (85). According to Critchley, this definition of the
public (of liberalism) attempts to ground the criterion for moral
obligation in a "sentient disposition that provokes compassion in
the face of the other's suffering" (90). This criterion, he
continues to argue, is found in Levinasian ethics--it is the ethical
relation to the other that takes place at the level of sensibility.
In addition, this criterion is found in Derrida's conception of
justice. As Critchley explains it, "Derrida paradoxically defines
justice as an experience of that which we are not able to
experience, which is qualified as 'the mystical', 'the impossible',
or 'aporia' . . . an 'experience' of the undecidable" (99). And for
Derrida, it is the experience of justice--of the unknowable--that
propels one forward into politics. Critchley is careful not to
suggest that Derrida locates justice in politics. To the contrary,
Derrida believes that no political decision can embody justice;
however, no political should be made without passing through the
aporia--the face to face--of justice. Critchley concludes, then,
that "what motivates the practice of deconstruction is an ethical
conception of justice, that is, by Rorty's criteria, public and
liberal" (102).
-
While he certainly does not collapse the distinction between ethics and politics
in this chapter, Critchley, through his interpretation of Derrida's
conception of justice, does cast doubt upon any kind of
ethics/politics polemic. Put another way, I think that by
destabilizing Rorty's private/public distinction, Critchley opens
up a space in which notions such as the "post-political" can be
examined and possibly understood in light of more nuanced
accounts of deconstruction. Moreover, Critchley's argument for a
Levinasian conception of subjectivity as the ethical basis of
deconstruction (even if it is a more cautious or reconstructed
argument) calls into question the kinds of subjectivity
(schizophrenic, sophistic, etc.) that some scholars see as part and
parcel of the poststructuralist deconstruction of the subject.
Like Critchley, many of these scholars theorize a new kind of
politics that comes after the ethical experience, after the
deconstructive aporia. Requisite to experiencing this aporia,
however, is a kind of Dionysian or Deleuzian subjectivity--an
unhinging of desires or an experience of the multiple within the
individual. The problem here, and it is a problem well illuminated
in chapter 3, is that in the space left by the exiled humanist,
metaphysical subject, these kinds of arguments insert yet another
metaphysical subject. In other words, this subject, as well as the
ethics derived from it, is something we can know and
control--something that we can enact or release at the level of
language by obfuscating meaning, identity, and representation. As a
result, the aporia is playfully characterized as a utopian dimension
of discourse--or worse, as an intellectual enterprise in which one
can participate through self-reflexive, parodic, paradoxical, and
digressive ways of writing. And it is by virtue of this
characterization that the subject, it seems, is once again reduced
to representation.
-
Critchley takes up this issue of representation, or thematization, in his
discussion of Levinasian ethics and psychoanalysis in chapter 8, "The Original Traumatism: Levinas and Psychoanalysis." Here
Critchley argues that Levinas attempts to articulate the relation to
the other in a series of "termes éthiques": accusation,
persecution, obsession, substitution, hostage, and trauma (184).
Like Levinas, Critchley points out that this attempt is an attempt
to thematize the unthematizable; it is a phenomenology of the
unphenomenologizable (184). Quite contrary to Levinas, however,
Critchley sees this language as indicative of a psychoanalytic
understanding of the unconscious. Of particular interest to
Critchley is Levinas's use of the term "trauma." He writes,
"Levinas tries to thematize the subject that is, according to me,
the condition of possibility for the ethical relation with the
notion of trauma. He thinks the subject as trauma--ethics is a
traumatology" (185).
-
Critchley's question to Levinas (a question which he admits is in opposition to
Levinas's intentions) is: "What does it mean to think the subject--the
subject of
the unconscious--as trauma?" (188). To begin with, according to Critchley,
thinking the Levinasian subject as trauma means that the ethical relation "takes
place at the level of pre-reflective sensibility and not at the level of
reflective consciousness" (188). More specifically, and based on the
"Substitution" chapter of Otherwise than Being, Critchley writes
that the subject as trauma is a subject utterly responsible for the suffering
that it undergoes--it is a subject of persecution, outrage, and suffering. He
later describes this original traumatism as a deafening traumatism, as "that
towards which I relate in passivity that exceeds representation, i.e. that
exceeds the intentional act of consciousness, that cannot be experienced as an
object" (190). "In other terms," he continues, "the subject is
constituted--without its knowledge, prior to cognition and recognition--in a
relation that exceeds representation, intentionality, symmetry, correspondence,
coincidence, equality and reciprocity, that is to say, to any form of ontology,
whether phenomenological or dialectical" (190).
-
Despite Levinas' resistance to psychoanalytic theory, Critchley believes that his
conceptions of the subject and the ethical relation depend on, to put it in
Lacanian terms, "a relation to the real, through the non-intentional affect of
jouissance, where the original traumatism of the other is the Thing,
das Ding" (190). Without this notion or mechanism of trauma, Critchley
claims, there would be no ethics in the Levinasian sense of the word (195).
Taking this connection further, he writes that "without a relation to trauma, or
at least without a relation to that which claims, calls, commands, summons,
interrupts or troubles the subject . . . there would no ethics, neither an
ethics of phenomenology, nor an ethics of psychoanalysis" (195). Finally,
foreshadowing his argument in chapter 12, Critchley contends that without
this ethical relation, one could not conceive a politics that would refuse the
category of totality. It is the absence of this ethical relation--this passivity
towards the other--that seems to limit, if not debilitate, so many other recent
discussions of ethics, politics, and subjectivity.
-
In chapter 12, "The Other's Decision in Me (What are the Politics of
Friendship?)," Critchley focuses primarily on the question of a non-totalizing
politics, positioning his previous discussions of subjectivity as a context for
his argument. As he explains early in the essay, through a reading of Blanchot's
Friendship, as well as a reading of Derrida's reading of Blanchot in
The Politics of Friendship, Critchley examines this question in
regard to Derrida's recent Adieu to Emmanuel Levinas. By way of
this discussion of friendship, and its relation to the public and the private
and to politics, Critchley argues that despite the connections between Derrida's
conception of "sur-vivance" (his attempt to think a nontraditional conception of
the passive decision of friendship that is linked to mortality) and Levinas's
ethical relation to the other, there is an important distance between Derrida's
work and that of Levinas. Critchley sees this distance as the result of five
problems in Levinas: (1) the idea of fraternity, (2) the question of God, (3) his
androcentric conception of friendship, (4) the relation of friendship to the
"family schema," and (5) the political fate of Levinasian ethics in regards to
the question of Israel (273-74).
-
With these problems in mind, Critchley goes on to provide a positive reading of
Derrida's position on politics in Adieu. According to Critchley,
although Derrida recognizes the gap in Levinas's work in regard to the path from
the ethical to the political, he does not read it as paralysis or resignation.
On the contrary, this hiatus, says Critchley, "allows Derrida both to affirm
the primacy of an ethics of hospitality, whilst leaving open the sphere of the
political as a realm of risk and danger" (275). It is this danger that allows
for what Derrida refers to as "political invention"--an invention or creation
that arises from "a response to the utter singularity of a particular and
inexhaustible context" (276). Critchley then describes this response as both
non-foundational and non-arbitrary--which is to say that it is a response that is
both unknowable and passive. It is in this respect that Critchley relates
political invention to Derrida's nontraditional conception of friendship, his
notion of "the other's decision is made in me" (277). In summary Critchley
writes that "what we seem to have here is a relation between friendship and
democracy, or ethics and politics . . . which leaves the decision open for
invention whilst acknowledging that the decision comes from the other" (277).
-
As I have argued throughout this review, it is the acknowledgment of the other
that distinguishes Ethics, Politics, Subjectivity from so many
other
works on subjectivity, ethics, and politics. Without this acknowledgment, that
is, without being affected by a consideration of the incomprehensible or
unthematizable, these works risk a kind of totality--they risk saying what the
subject is (a fragmented stream of desires) and what it isn't (a unified,
coherent self). That they can know undermines their discussions of the other,
reducing it at times to a trope. This is not to say that all discussions of
subjectivity, ethics, and politics must be Levinasian. However, since they tend
to use this term, "other," in addition to many Derridian terms, in order to wage
war on metaphysics, the Enlightenment, and humanism, it seems that closer
readings of deconstruction, subjectivity, ethics, and politics are called for.
Critchley has begun to answer that call.
Rhetoric and Composition Program
English Department
Purdue University
penderk@purdue.edu
COPYRIGHT (c) 2002 BY Kelly Pender.
READERS MAY USE PORTIONS
OF THIS WORK IN ACCORDANCE WITH THE FAIR USE PROVISIONS OF U.S. COPYRIGHT
LAW. IN ADDITION, SUBSCRIBERS AND MEMBERS OF SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTIONS MAY
USE THE ENTIRE WORK FOR ANY INTERNAL NONCOMMERCIAL PURPOSE BUT, OTHER THAN
ONE COPY SENT BY EMAIL, PRINT OR FAX TO ONE PERSON AT ANOTHER LOCATION FOR
THAT INDIVIDUAL'S PERSONAL USE, DISTRIBUTION OF THIS ARTICLE OUTSIDE OF A
SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION FROM EITHER THE
AUTHOR OR THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS IS EXPRESSLY FORBIDDEN.
THIS ARTICLE AND OTHER CONTENTS OF THIS ISSUE ARE
AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE UNTIL RELEASE OF THE NEXT ISSUE. A
TEXT-ONLY ARCHIVE OF THE JOURNAL IS ALSO AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE. FOR
FULL HYPERTEXT ACCESS TO BACK ISSUES, SEARCH UTILITIES, AND OTHER VALUABLE
FEATURES, YOU OR YOUR INSTITUTION MAY SUBSCRIBE TO
PROJECT MUSE, THE
ON-LINE JOURNALS PROJECT OF THE JOHNS
HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS.
Works Cited
Llewelyn, John. The Middle Voice of Ecological Conscience: A
Chiasmic Reading of Responsibility in the Neighborhood of Levinas,
Heidegger, and Others. New York: St. Martin's P, 1991.
|