Review of:
Bruno Latour, Pandora's Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science
Studies. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1999.
- Scientists are becoming more attentive to and are addressing more openly
the relationships between politics and science. (Many scientists have of
course--at least since Galileo, if not Archimedes or even the pre-Socratics--been
aware of and had to confront the complexity of these relationships.) As I am
writing this review, I am reading a commentary by Roger A. Pielke Jr., "Science
Policy: Policy, Politics, and Perspective," in the current issue of
Nature (28 March 2002), dealing with these relationships in their, I
would argue, postmodern specificity, as does Bruno Latour's
Pandora's Hope. The timing of the Nature article could
not be more auspicious for this review, but other examples, articles, and books,
technical and popular, are not hard to come by.
-
It is difficult to say to what degree this increased attention is specifically due
to the influence of what is known as science studies or social, or sometimes
social-constructivist, studies of science, a controversial field that has emerged
during the last several decades and to which Latour's work largely belongs. It is
also not altogether clear how much this attention was influenced by the
controversies themselves around science studies, most recently the so-called
"Science Wars." The latter followed the appearance of Paul Gross and Norman
Levitt's book Higher Superstition: The Academic Left and its Quarrels with
Science (1994), theoretical physicist Alan Sokal's hoax article published
in the journal Social Text (1995), and Impostures
intellectueles (1998), co-authored by Sokal and another theoretical
physicist, Jean Bricmont, first published in France, and then in England and the
U.S., under the title Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern Intellectuals' Abuse
of Science (1998). Latour has been a prominent subject of and participant
in the Science Wars debates, beginning with Gross and Levitt's book, and through
Latour's responses to his critics, including those in Pandora's Hope
(some among the essays included in the book have been published earlier). Some of
these debates have been conducted in scientific journals, such as
Nature and Physics Today, and have involved leading
scientists. Accordingly, they may have had an impact (it is, again, difficult to
say how large) on the proliferating discussions of the relationships between
politics and science in the scientific community. It would be hard, however, to
underestimate other factors involved, from increasing competition for funding to
the problems of bioethics; these may indeed be the more significant ones.
-
Be that as it may, Latour's work and arguments, as presented in the
book, could help scientists and others who want to understand the complexity,
"the Gordian knot," as Latour called it in his earlier We Have Never Been
Modern, of the postmodern entanglement of politics and science. Indeed,
the three problem phenomena invoked by the Nature article just
cited, under the fitting heading "Gridlock"--"global climate change," "nuclear
power," and "biodiversity" (367)--are paradigmatically Latourian, and the first is specifically invoked by him in We Have Never Been Modern. That
need not mean that scientists or others must agree with Latour's analysis
(the
present author does not always either). But they might do well to engage with it
properly, or at least to stay with it for more than a sentence or two, the usual
limit of most "science warriors," which also applies to other postmodernists they
"read." I am not sure how much hope--this may be a kind of Pandora's hope in
turn--one might hold here, and sometimes the Pandora's-box nature of these works,
Latour's included, complicates their chances. I am not sure that
humanists, especially historians, sociologists, and philosophers of science, will
always give Latour the chance he deserves either. I hope they will.
-
Beyond serving as a useful introduction to the current stage of science studies
and as a commentary on the Science Wars (and it is, again, worth reading for the
sake of these subjects alone), Pandora's Hope pursues, with many
notable successes, at least three ambitious and interconnected tasks. The first
is to redefine the concept of reality by using the research undertaken in science
studies; the second is to rethink the relationships between science and politics
in modern (ultimately extending from Plato) and then postmodern culture; and the
third is to redefine political philosophy--indeed, Latour appears to suggest,
even to define it meaningfully for the first time. These tasks are
interconnected in part because the phenomena in question are, Latour rightly
argues, themselves irreducibly interconnected. In particular, there can be no
modernity or postmodernity other than scientific, as science was irreducibly
involved with setting up what Latour calls, in We Have Never Been
Modern, "the modern constitution," which unequivocally separated nature
and politics. Or rather, the moderns only claim (and can only claim)
to separate them, since such a separation is, in principle, impossible, as both
are ultimately entangled in any phenomena, scientific or political. Hence,
Latour's title, We Have Never Been Modern. Pandora's
Hope builds on and deepens this argument.
- The book has some key "postmodern" allies, in particular Michel
Serres, Gilles Deleuze (in part via Isabelle Stengers's work) and
Jean-François Lyotard, who, while mentioned only in passing, may be more
important for the book than it might appear. Indeed, I would argue that Latour's
work is much more postmodern, at least in Lyotard's sense, than he is willing to
acknowledge. Latour's argument that "we have never been modern" can be
coordinated with Lyotard's famous maxim that the postmodern precedes the modern,
in a pre-logical rather than ontological sense. This sense is defined by a
complex underlying ("postmodern") dynamics that both gives rise to and is
suppressed or repressed by the modern, not unlike the way in which the hybrid or
the "factish" (combining "fact" and "fetish") are repressed by the moderns'
unequivocal separations (into nature and politics, into facts and fetishes) in
Latour. This kind of postmodernism, that is, the one that is both Lyotardian and
Latourian (keeping in mind the differences between Lyotard's and Latour's views),
helps the richness and effectiveness of Latour's analysis, rather than misses its
arguments, as some postmodernisms, or at least some postmodernists,
indeed might. Reciprocally, Latour's analysis enriches and expands our
understanding of postmodern culture and the role of science and technology in it.
- The book has nine hefty chapters (and a substantial conclusion).
The first, "Do You Believe in Reality?: News from the Trenches of the Science
War," serves as an introduction and a set-up, but it is significant in its own
right in giving its title question a necessary complexity and a necessary
ambiguity, or in Niels Bohr's phrase "essential ambiguity," without which one
cannot perhaps refer to any form of ultimate reality. The next four chapters are
case studies, vintage Latour and engrossing reading, but with significant
philosophical twists. Two of them, Chapters 4 and 5, extend Latour's justly
famous work on Louis Pasteur. Latour's work is arguably the best that science
studies has to offer us, in part given its greater philosopher charge, which
contrasts with most other works in this generally more empiricist field. The case
studies also ground and prepare the last three, more philosophical, chapters, on
which I shall primarily concentrate here. These chapters define the book's
achievement as a contribution to the current state of the debates concerning the
relationships between science and culture, politics included. The Science Wars
are, Latour argues, a reflection and an effect of this role.
-
Indeed, as he became arguably the main target of the Science Wars scientific
critics, at least as far as science studies are concerned (Lacan, Deleuze, and,
overt disclaimers to the contrary, Derrida, are targeted for their
"postmodernist" abuses of science), Latour gets hold of some among the deeper
underlying forces involved in shaping the confrontation.
Reciprocally, however,
these forces define the postmodern philosophical, cultural, and political scene.
As I said, the grounds for both this insight into the Science Wars and the
underlying play of forces in question are prepared in We Have Never Been
Modern and, to some degree, already in Conversations on Science,
Culture, and Time by Serres and Latour. The workings of these forces are
now traced to Plato's Gorgias (not coincidentally, Lyotard discusses
Gorgias, the philosopher, in The Differend as well), in Chapter 7,
"The Inventions of the Science War: The Settlement of Socrates and Callicles"
and in Chapter 8, "A Politics Freed from Science: The Body Cosmopolitics."
-
Stephen Weinberg's comment in his "Sokal's Hoax," parallel to Socrates's
(broader) view of the role of geometry in the world (human and divine) in
Gorgias, provides a fitting point of departure: "Our civilization
has been powerfully affected by the discovery that nature is strictly governed by
impersonal laws....We will need to confirm and strengthen the vision of a
rationally understandable world if we are to protect ourselves from the
irrational tendencies that still best humanity" (216). Weinberg is not wrong in
the first part of this statement, although one could, and Latour does, assess the
value and significance of this impact differently. The impact itself may indeed
be traced to the Greeks' invention of mathematics rather than, as in Weinberg's
narrower context, to the invention of modern (mathematical) physics by Galileo
and, especially, by Newton. It is Weinberg's second statement, or rather the
conjunction of both statements thus defined, that is Latour's primary target.
Alan Sokal's "serious" "political," including his "Marxist," arguments, may
be shown to follow the same "logic" (quotation marks appear obligatory here). To
the degree, which is large, that this conjunction defines the Science Wars, one
can indeed trace their invention to Plato's Gorgias, defined by "the
strong link...between the respect for impersonal natural laws, on the one hand,
and the fight against irrationality, immorality, and political disorder, on the
other" (217). More accurately, in Socrates's case one would speak of the
universal laws (of geometry), more those of mind than of nature, and Weinberg, in
fairness, does not claim a role for mathematics beyond science, as his immediate
context is more narrowly and differently defined. Essentially, however, Latour's
argument stands, given the deeper underpinning of Weinberg's argument. Indeed
Latour's immediate elaboration nearly makes the case. He writes:
In both quotations the fate of Reason and the fate of Politics are associated in
a single destiny. To attack Reason is to render morality and social peace
impossible. Right is what protects us against Might; Reason against civil
warfare. The common tenet is that we need something "inhuman"--for Weinberg,
the natural law no human has constructed; for Socrates, geometry whose
demonstrations escape human whim--if we want to be able to fight against
"inhumanity." To sum up: only inhumanity will quash inhumanity. Only a
Science that is not made by man will protect a Body Politic that is in constant
risk of being made by the mob. Yes, Reason is our rampart, our Great Wall of
China, our Maginot Line against the dangerous unruly mob. (217)
-
What is perhaps most remarkable about this, one might say, naïve view,
naïve as
concerns both science or mathematics (for example, in applying to nature,
including the nature of mind, a human, "all too human," concept of law) and
politics, or the relationships between them, is that it has been so successful.
For, as Latour immediately observes, "this line of reasoning, which I will call
'inhumanity against inhumanity,' has been attacked ever since it began, from the
Sophists, against whom Plato launches his all-out assault, all the way to the
motley gang of people accused of 'postmodernism' (an accusation, by the way, as
vague as the curse of being a 'sophist')" (217). Indeed the two accusations are
often vaguely combined. There is no simple answer to the question why these
counterarguments have more often failed than succeeded, and it would,
accordingly, be difficult to blame Latour for not really pursuing the subject in the book.
But he could have. This relative lack of success, admittedly, gives the other
side of the Science Wars additional ammunition that is philosophically feeble but
politically workable. Admittedly, too, many of these counterarguments have been
equally deficient, philosophically and politically. Indeed, according to Latour,
most (all?) of them have failed in at least one respect, something he aims to
remedy: "None of these critiques...has disputed simultaneously the
definition of Science and the definition of the Body Politic that it
implies. Inhumanity is accepted in both or in at least one of them" (218).
-
This assessment does not appear to me entirely accurate, even with respect to
what Latour sees as "postmodern" critique and specifically to Friedrich
Nietzsche, who, perhaps inevitably, enters the scene immediately, first by way of
quotation, "human all too human," and then by name (217). Nietzsche's argument
in On the Genealogy of Morals, invoked throughout the chapter, is
not sufficiently explored by Latour, either. Nietzsche's and Latour's views are
of course not the same, but, especially on this particular point, they share more
than Latour appears to think. The philosophical effectiveness of any given
argument, however, does not necessarily guarantee and sometimes prevents its
success anywhere, among people or philosophers, for example, as indeed both
Socrates (including in Gorgias, as Latour observes) and, more
deeply, Nietzsche understood so well. Beginning with The Birth of
Tragedy, Nietzsche undertook an investigation, unprecedented in profundity
and scope alike, of the question why Socrates's or related and parallel arguments
(those shaping the history of Christian morality, for example) have, eventually,
succeeded on such an extraordinary scale, including where they initially failed,
in Greece.
- Similarly, Lyotard's argument from The Postmodern
Condition on goes quite far in understanding the "humanity," indeed
conjoined "humanity" rather than conjoined "inhumanity," of both science and
politics, that is, speaking for the moment in terms Latour uses. Ultimately, to
return to the idiom of We Have Never Been Modern, we need a new
"constitution," one that, as against the (unworkable) "modern constitution,"
enacts a conjunction rather than a strict separation of nature and politics, and
even a certain "parliamentarity" of the human and the nonhuman. In
Pandora's Hope Latour approaches this economy, which is also a
political economy, in other terms as well, such as those of the collective (of
humans and nonhumans), specifically in Chapter 6, indebted in part to the work of
Michel Callon (with whom Latour collaborated earlier), and also in "factish"
("fact-fetish") in Chapter 9. This view is not far from Lyotard's, even though
Latour himself, again, juxtaposes it to postmodernism. Lyotard's own concept of
"the inhuman," developed in his The Inhuman: Reflections on
Time,
could be considered from this viewpoint and used to complement and amplify
Latour's critique. On the other hand, Latour seems to give Lyotard credit, well
deserved indeed, for his engagement with the political in his subsequent works,
specifically along the lines of Latour's argument here (232). These works,
however, such as Just Gaming and The Differend, extend
rather than depart from his argument in The Postmodern Condition. As
I said, Latour is much more "postmodernist" than he suspects. Reciprocally,
Latour's argument throws a new light on postmodernism and the debates around it,
or within it, for example, concerning the more Lyotardian view of postmodernist
epistemology and politics versus more Marxist views, such as those of Fredric
Jameson and his followers. In the latter case, a Socratic-like agenda of the
governing role of a particular, almost geometrically demonstrable, political
theory, often takes over.
- It may be noted that even short of a deeper analysis of its human
or human-nonhuman nature, one could argue that, at least, modern or "postmodern"
(the term has been used even by some scientists) mathematics and science are not
as cooperative in the agenda in question as, for example, Weinberg would believe
them to be. Even if one accepts Weinberg's position and views modern mathematics
and science in his "inhuman" terms, they appear to tell us something quite
different from what Weinberg seems to hear. Indeed more limited as it is, this
type of counterargument has a force of its own. The grounds on which the science
warriors, from Socrates on, build their edifice are, Latour is right, untenable;
but their argument fails, their edifice collapses even on its own ground. Lyotard
offers this type of argument as part of his critique of modernity's ideology of
science in The Postmodern Condition (a critique that has
often been
misunderstood, including by the science warriors). If, he argues, one wants to
follow mathematics and science or what they tell us about nature and mind, in the
way the Enlightenment follows classical mathematics and physics, one might want to
examine first what twentieth-century mathematics and science--relativity, quantum
physics, chaos theory, modern molecular biology and genetics, post-Gödelian
mathematical logic, and so forth--actually tell us. More accurately, one should
speak of a certain version or reading of the Enlightenment, to begin with, since
both the Enlightenment and, for that matter, classical mathematics and science
tell us a different story and a different history as well.
-
In any event, what mathematics and science in fact appear to tell us
(about nature or themselves) is in conflict with the key premises of the modern
(either in Lyotard's or Latour's sense) view or ideology of either mathematics
and science or nature and politics. Among these premises are reality and
causality (concomitantly defined by their mathematical, and specifically
continuous, character); the independence of this mathematical, and indeed
geometrical, reality of our engagement with nature through observation and
measurement; a strictly logical view of mathematical reasoning (i.e., as
always
decidable as concerns the truth or falsity of any given proposition); and so
forth. These premises and their necessity for the practice of mathematics and
science have been questioned by some (it is true, not very many) mathematicians
and scientists as well, in particular by Bohr, Heisenberg, and other founders of
quantum physics, which puts these premises to their arguably most severe test on
scientific grounds. The same premises also define the key programs of the
Enlightenment and "the modern constitution," based on the ("inhuman") way in
which mathematics and science, or nature and politics, allegedly work or, in the
case of politics, ought to work. It follows, among other things, that contrary
to Weinberg's view or hope, nature may not in fact be subject to immutable, or
any, mathematical laws. It goes almost without saying that to question
such premises is not the same as simply abandoning them, but instead enables a
better understanding of the limits of their applicability, a refinement of their
conceptualization and formulations, and so forth. I say "almost" in view of
persistent misunderstandings of this and related points, including those made by
Latour himself, the misunderstandings that defined and in some ways (there are
deeper philosophical and political factors, which is the point here) initiated
the Science Wars debates.
-
Latour amplifies the preceding argument by his powerful and elegant analysis, one
of the best in the book, in Chapter 8, "A Politics Freed from Science:
The Body Cosmopolitics," concerning the actual practice of science, which he
sees, rightly, as in conflict with the Science Warriors', the Socrates-Weinberg,
view of science. This argument also allows one to
see...how the sciences can be
free from the burden of making a type of politics that shortcuts politics. If we
now calmly read the Gorgias, we recognize that a certain specialized
form of reasoning, epistèmè, was kidnapped for a political
purpose it could not possibly fulfill. This has resulted in bad politics but in
an even worse science. If we let the kidnapped science escape, then two
different meanings of the adjective "scientific" become distinguishable again
after being lumped together for so long. (258)
The implications of this
argument thus reach beyond our understanding of science, although not beyond
science, which cannot be dissociated from modern politics--and there is perhaps no
other politics, beginning with the Greeks and their invention of demonstration
and democracy. As will be seen, for Latour, bringing science and politics, and
demonstration and democracy, together so that both they and we could indeed
benefit from each other is a task, a formidable "task of today" (265). First,
however, we need to consider the two different meanings of "scientific" in
question. As Latour writes:
The first meaning is that of Science with a capital S, the ideal of
transportation of information without discussion or deformation. This Science,
capital S, is not a description of what scientists do. To use an old
term, it is an ideology that never had any other use, in the epistemologists'
hands, than to offer a substitute for public discussion. It has always
been a political weapon to do away with the constraints of politics. From the
beginning, as we saw in the dialogue, it was tailored to this end alone, and it
has never stopped, through the ages, being used in this way.
Because it was intended as a weapon, this conception of Science, the one Weinberg
clings to so forcefully, is usable neither to "make humanity less irrational" nor
to make the sciences better. It has only one use: "Keep your mouth shut!"--the
"you" designating, interestingly enough, other scientists involved in
controversies as much as the people in general. "Substitute Science, capital S,
for political rationality" is only a war cry. In that sense, and that sense
only, it is useful, as we can witness in these days of the Science Wars.
However, this definition of Science No. 1, I am afraid, has no more uses than a
Maginot Line, and I take great pleasure in being branded as "antiscientific"
if scientific has only this meaning. (258-59)
-
The actual situation may be somewhat more complex, since Weinberg's view of
science (but not of politics) could be related to what scientists actually do, as
Latour acknowledges in his discussion of the second meaning of "scientific," but
to which one might give further attention (259). In this sense, it is indeed the
ideology in question that is the main problem here. Paul Feyerabend sees this
move--this tremendous and impoverishing, "cold," reduction of science and, through
thus reduced science, of politics or even of life itself--as "the tale of
abstraction against the richness of being," his subtitle of Conquest of
Abundance. He traces
this move to the pre-Socratics, especially to Democritus's atomism and Parmenides's
logic of oneness, and, ethically-politically, to Homer (on virtue), and then
to the modern view of science, from Newton to Einstein and beyond. (Weinberg's
view would be an example as well.) Keats drives the point home more speedily and
effectively in Lamia (with Socrates, and his philosophy, and both
Descartes and Newton, and their optics, in mind, and perhaps with Democritus and
Boyle
as well, all figures crucial to Latour's argument, here and elsewhere): "... Do
not all charms fly/ At the mere touch of cold philosophy? ... Philosophy will
clip an Angel's wings/ Conquer all mysteries by rule and line,/ Empty the haunted
air ..." (Part II, ll. 229-30, 234-35).
-
At least, a certain philosophy and/as a certain form or ideology of mathematics
and science, since the latter views pursued differently (or even also
differently) could also create "the richness of being," even by their rules and
lines. "But," Latour continues, "'scientific' has one other meaning, which is
much more interesting and is not engaged in doing away with politics,
not because it is apolitical or because it is politicized, but because
it deals with entirely different questions, a difference that is never respected
when Science No. 1 is taken, by its friends as well as by its foes, as
all there is to say about science" (259). It is, thus, first of all, not a
question of an argument or discourse against science, quite the contrary.
Latour's conception of science (or, and again comcomitantly, of reality or truth)--one of his most important and original in the book--also goes beyond earlier
and more rigid forms of social constructivism, such as that of David Bloor and
his school (197). This richer and subtler "constructivism" is arrived at in part
by reciprocally rethinking the social as well, most especially through the
concept of the collective of human and nonhumans, and of their entangled and
mutually defining relationships, in Chapter 6. As Latour writes:
The second meaning of the adjective "scientific" is the gaining of access,
through experiments and calculations, to entities that at first do not have the
same characteristics as humans do. This definition may seem odd, but it is what
is alluded to by Weinberg's own interest in "impersonal laws." Science No. 2
deals with nonhumans, which in the beginning are foreign to social life, and
which are slowly socialized on our midst through the channels of laboratories,
expeditions, institutions, and so on, as recent historians of science have so
often described. What working scientists want to be sure of is that they do
not make up, with their own repertoire of actions, the new entities to which
they have access. They want each new nonhuman to enrich their repertoire of
action, their ontology. Pasteur, for example, does not [arbitrarily] "construct"
his microbes; rather his microbes, and French society, are changed, through their
common agency, from a collective [of humans and nonhumans] made up of, say, x
entities into one made up of many more entities, including microbes.
(259)
- This argument may need a more nuanced stratification as concerns
the production and circulation in question, as Latour indeed intimates (259). In
particular, one might need to consider multiple circulations of and circulations
between circulations, within science and between science and culture. It is also
clear that these profusions or circulations within circulations are bound to give
rise to other meanings of "scientific" as well. Latour adds one himself (260,
note 3), but still others, either more limited to science or mathematics or more
extended, are conceivable and indeed necessary. Latour's argument is, however,
fundamentally right and momentous in its implications. First of all, it follows
that there could be neither a concept of reality nor a meaningful relation to any
reality outside such circulations. Accordingly, all "realities" of science
studies (such as those defined by various collectives of humans and nonhumans,
hybrids, factishes, and so forth) in turn emerge in relation to these
circulations. This view also makes "it possible to say, without contradiction,"
as Latour does in his analysis of Pasteur, "both 'Airborne germs were made up in
1984' and 'They were there all along'" (173). The same logic applies to several
of his similar arguments elsewhere, often equally misunderstood or unread, for
example, by science warriors.
-
Indeed one of the most remarkable capacities of modern science, specifically
quantum theory, is to "construct" (using this terms with Latour's qualification
in the above passage in mind) and place in circulation unconstructible
entities (such as those known as "elementary particles"). That is, it is capable of
constructing and placing in circulation something to which no conceivable notion
or property, physical or mathematical, could be rigorously attributed. They are
circulated as such both within and outside physics, albeit far from without much
resistance to this type of epistemology, either within science (Einstein was one
the primary forces of this resistance and inspiration for many others) or outside
it. It is not surprising that the idea meets so much resistance since, as I
have indicated, it puts on hold the claims, such as Weinberg's, that "nature"
could ultimately be described or governed by mathematics. This is, of course, not
to say that one no longer uses mathematics, but only that one uses it
differently, including for the purposes of circulating the work concerning such
un-objects.
- From a Latourian perspective, Weinberg's or others'
"interests,"
grounding (but not identical to) their view of science as
Science No. 1, would be part of such circulations, possibly by grounding some
among them. But this view must also be understood in relation to other
circulations, possible or actual, or of course also to impossibilities of
circulation. The same argument would apply to mathematics (so crucial for
Weinberg's or Socrates's views of the world), to mathematical circulation, and to
the circulation of mathematics itself (as a field). Mathematics may well be a
special case, including (a special case of its own) specifically geometrical
demonstration or proof, and we must account for this specificity, in turn, in a
special way. But it is not outside of this picture. Mathematics is not likely to
be some special gift from the "heavens" (divine or human), although some
mathematicians, scientists, and philosophers may think it is. Instead, like science
or philosophy, it may be seen as having arisen and continuing to arise
from translating and refining more common experiences and practices, and
from circulations they entail or that give rise to them.
-
As Latour elegantly argues in Chapter 3, "Circulating Reference," the work of
science studies, such as Latour's own, participates differently from
but reciprocally with science itself in these circulations and
circulations of circulation (78-79). This circulation is contiguous
or metonymic. A remarkable case of a circulation, indeed a
circulation between, at least, two circulations, where reciprocity
and metonymy are accompanied by metaphoric parallels, is that of
Frederic Joliot, considered in Chapter 3, "Science's Blood Flow:
Joliot's Scientific Intelligence." Latour's title is aptly fitting
on both counts, in its circulation metaphor and its blood metaphor.
Circulation is the life-blood of science, which also needs what
exceeds it. (Latour also puns on "intelligence.") I ought to add,
however, that this argument is only a part, a small part, of this
superb chapter, which offers a brilliant and complex analysis of a
complex case, defined as much by Joliot's political as by his
scientific activities, and by the complex circulations between
science and politics. This economy, Latour shows, defines Joliot's
work well before he becomes (after the Second World War) a prominent
presence on the political scene in France and beyond.
-
Now, the analysis of such circulations and circulations between circulations is
not easy, either in their historical specificity or (to the degree we can
separate them) in terms of the necessary concepts, and Latour's analysis by and
large succeeds on both counts. But he seems to me stronger on the work and
abundance
of circulations than on "breaks" in circulations or the impossibility of
circulation or "construction," in mathematics and science or
elsewhere, which seems to me just as important, in some cases, more important.
In general, Latour's thought is closer to what may be seen as the (more utopian?)
philosophy of abundance and continuity, which also defines the thought of
Feyerabend and Deleuze, or Whitehead and Bergson, or earlier Leibniz and Spinoza
(the last three in turn major inspirations for Deleuze). This philosophy may be
contrasted to the philosophy of insufficiency and rupture, extending from Kant's
critical philosophy to Heidegger, Bataille, Levinas, Derrida, and de Man, among
others. Descartes, Hegel, and Nietzsche may be seen as the thinkers of both, and
it is to be observed that in all these cases it is also a question of relative
balance, rather than unequivocal determination. Allegiances to the first and,
conversely, distances from the second line of thought are quite apparent in
Latour's views--sometimes, I would argue, at a price, and especially, again, as
concerns a more rigorous understanding of heterogeneities and breaks in the
circulations in question. On that score, Latour's analysis could benefit from the
ideas of the figures just mentioned, especially Bataille, Derrida, de Man, or,
again, Lyotard (specifically on "the inhuman"). Lyotard defines the political as
the irreducible heterogeneous, even if interactive--interactively heterogeneous
and heterogeneously interactive--and subject to equally irreducible breaks in its
circulations. Latour, however, is quite right to insist on the significance of
circulation, especially insofar as the relationships between science and
politics, or culture, are concerned. His analysis of such circulations, their
rhizomatic networks, and circulations between circulations, networks linking
networks, is a major contribution, whose significance extends well beyond science
studies.
-
Latour is also right in arguing that "to do justice to this scientific work," the
work defined as Science No. 2, (the ideology of) Science No. 1 is "totally
inadequate" (260). He adds a significant observation:
We recognize here, by the way, the two enemy camps between which science studies
is trying to gain a foothold: those from the humanities who think we give too
much to nonhumans; and those from some quarters of the "hard" sciences who accuse
us of giving too much to the humans. This symmetrical accusation triangulates
with great precision the place where we in science studies stand: we follow
scientists in their daily scientific practice in the No. 2 definition, not in the
No. 1 political definition. Reason--meaning Science No. 1--does not describe
science better than cynicism describes politics. (260)
-
This statement, again, makes clear a crucial point. It is not a
matter of a discourse against science, any more than
against reality or truth, but rather that of refiguring and
re-delimiting both and their relationships, in their relationships,
naturally, as against, the ideology, ultimately itself
non-scientific, although political, of Science No. 1. This is a
brilliant reversal with respect to the attacks (such as those by the
science warriors) against science studies. It is the science
warriors' view of science that is in fact political and not
scientific; the science studies political view of science will be
shown to be more scientific.
-
Nor is this all, as we now begin to perceive Latour's ultimate, and quite
elegant, logic more clearly. First of all, it is worth reiterating yet another
more obvious and more easily apparent reversal. The "politics" of science
warriors, let's call it Politics or, with Latour, the Social No. 1, is not really
political or social, any more than their science, Science No. 1, is
scientific. Science No. 2 is more political as well, along with being
scientific. It is, however, by combining both reversals that Latour's logic
reaches its ultimate conclusions. The form, the formal logic, as it were, of
Socrates's argument is in fact repeated. Science is indeed crucial to and
defines politics, which might, finally (might!) enable us "to benefit from the
Greeks' two inventions, demonstration and democracy" (265). But how different is
the substance of both politics and science, and of their relationships, and,
hence, how different is the political philosophy one now needs to pursue! For,
thanks in large measure to what Science No. 2 could do for politics, this new
constitution entails a very different social, or in Serres's terms,
natural or social-natural contract and a new collectivity and, in the language of
We Have Never Been Modern, a new "parliamentarity" of both humans
and nonhumans. Latour writes:
Far from taking us away from the agora, Science No. 2--one clearly separated from
the impossible agenda of Science, capital S--redefines political order as that
which brings together stars, prions, cows, heavens, and people, the task being to
turn this collective into a "cosmos" instead of "unruly shambles" [as invoked by
Socrates]. For scientists such an endeavor seems much more lively, much more
interesting, much more adapted to their skills and genius, than the boring
repetitive chore of beating the poor undisciplined demos with the big stick of
"impersonal laws." This new settlement is not the one Socrates and Callicles
agreed on [in Gorgias ]--"appealing to one form of inhumanity to
avoid inhuman social behavior"--but something that could be defined as
"collectively making sure that the collective formed by ever vaster numbers of
humans and nonhumans becomes a cosmos." (261)
- Naturally, this new politics is not easy to put into practice.
(But then it took Socratic politics, defined by Science No. 1, a while to take a
hold, indeed a grip, upon the world.) For, as Latour says,
For this other possible task, however, we not only need scientists who will
abandon the older privileges of Science No. 1 and at last take up a
science (No. 2) freed from politics [Politics No. 1, defined by
Science No. 1], we also need a symmetrical transformation of
politics. I confess that this is much more difficult, because, in
practice, very few scientists are happy in the artificial
straitjacket that Socrates's position imposes on them, and they
would be very happy to deal with what they are good at, Science
No. 2. But what about politics? To convince Socrates is one things,
but what about Callicles? To free science from politics [Politics
No. 1] is easy, but how can we free politics from science [No. 1]?
(261)
-
Latour may be too optimistic about scientists. He is right, however, to see
politics as a more difficult problem here. Latour makes few
suggestions in this direction, in this and in the following chapter.
In the end, however, we, Latour and myself included, end with a
question:
How can we mix Science No. 2, which brings an ever greater number of nonhumans
into the agora, with Social No. 2, which deals with the very specific conditions
of felicity that cannot be content with transporting forces or truth without
deformation? I don't know, but I am sure of one thing: no shortcuts are
possible, no short-circuits, and no acceleration. Half of our knowledge may be
in the hands of scientists, but the other, missing half is alive only in those
most despised of all people, the politicians, who are risking their lives and
ours in scientifico-political controversies that nowadays make up most of our
daily bread. To deal with these controversies, a "double circulation" has to
flow effortlessly again in the Body Politics: the one of science (No. 2) free
from politics, and the other of politics freed from science (No.
1). The task of
today may be summed up in the following odd sentence: Can we learn to like
scientists as much as politicians so that at last we can benefit from
the Greeks' two inventions, demonstration and democracy? (265)
-
Latour, it is true, does not end here, observing that, while he "seem[s] to have
accomplished [his] task, to have dismantled the old settlement that held sway
over us," "it is still as if [he has] achieved nothing" (266). Accordingly, he
proceeds to his final chapter, Chapter 9, "The Slight Surprise of Action: Facts,
Fetishes, Factishes," more constructive and more constructivist, but, again,
beyond (merely) "social constructivism," which he contends (I think, rightly) he
never really subscribed to (197). We, as the book's readers, can indeed be only
slightly surprised here, since Latour's analysis is well prepared and
anticipated, and partly accomplished in an earlier chapter, but is now given a
more rigorous conceptual architecture.
- And yet the questions return and even bring a war with them, "a
world war, even--at least a metaphysical one," but also the Science Wars, now as
"a respectable intellectual issue, not a pathetic dispute over funding fueled by
campus journalists." It is a war between the two views of reality and two
settlements in opposition, the modernist one (with the reality of the world out
there and Science No. 1 and Politics No. 1) and the settlement defined by the view
of reality, science, and politics that is defined by Science No. 2. In this war,
however, one might be sure, or "pretty sure,"
we will be without weapons, dressed in civilian clothes, since the task of
inventing the collective [of humans and nonhumans] is so formidable that it
renders all wars puny by comparison--including, of course, the Science Wars. In
this [twentieth] century, which fortunately is coming to a close, we seem to have
exhausted the evils that emerged from the open box of the clumsy Pandora. Though
it was here unrestrained curiosity that made the artificial maiden open the box,
there is no reason to stop being curious about what was left inside. To retrieve
the Hope that is lodged there, at the bottom, we need a new and rather convoluted
contrivance. I have had a go at it. Maybe we will succeed with the next
attempt. (300)
-
Maybe we will. Latour thus ends (this is his last sentence) with an implicit
question mark, for the new century perhaps. He begins the book with a warning to
the reader. "This," he says,
is not a book about new facts, nor is it exactly a
book of philosophy. In it, using only very rudimentary tools, I simply try to
present, in the space left empty by the dichotomy between subject and object, a
conceptual scenography for the pair human and nonhuman. I agree that powerful
arguments and detailed empirical studies would be better, but, as sometimes
happens in detective stories, a somewhat weaker, more solitary, and more
adventurous strategy may succeed against the kidnapping of scientific disciplines
by science warriors where others have failed. (viii)
The book does achieve this success and, as I have argued, it offers much more in
the way of both "powerful arguments" and, especially, "empirical studies" than
Latour here suggests. Accordingly, a deeper
conceptual and, thus, more deeply philosophical scenography of the scenes in
question is not impossible. It is perhaps permissible to view the
book as setting the stage for a deeper philosophical exploration in spaces
more closed than, as Latour suggests, left empty by so many dichotomies
and pairs, from subject and object to, not inconceivably, human and nonhuman.
Theory and Cultural Studies Program
Department of English
Purdue University
aplotnit@sla.purdue.edu
COPYRIGHT (c) 2002 BY Arkady Plotnitsky.
READERS MAY USE PORTIONS
OF THIS WORK IN ACCORDANCE WITH THE FAIR USE PROVISIONS OF U.S. COPYRIGHT
LAW. IN ADDITION, SUBSCRIBERS AND MEMBERS OF SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTIONS MAY
USE THE ENTIRE WORK FOR ANY INTERNAL NONCOMMERCIAL PURPOSE BUT, OTHER THAN
ONE COPY SENT BY EMAIL, PRINT OR FAX TO ONE PERSON AT ANOTHER LOCATION FOR
THAT INDIVIDUAL'S PERSONAL USE, DISTRIBUTION OF THIS ARTICLE OUTSIDE OF A
SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION FROM EITHER THE
AUTHOR OR THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS IS EXPRESSLY FORBIDDEN.
THIS ARTICLE AND OTHER CONTENTS OF THIS ISSUE ARE
AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE UNTIL RELEASE OF THE NEXT ISSUE. A
TEXT-ONLY ARCHIVE OF THE JOURNAL IS ALSO AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE. FOR
FULL HYPERTEXT ACCESS TO BACK ISSUES, SEARCH UTILITIES, AND OTHER VALUABLE
FEATURES, YOU OR YOUR INSTITUTION MAY SUBSCRIBE TO
PROJECT MUSE, THE
ON-LINE JOURNALS PROJECT OF THE JOHNS
HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS.
Works Cited
Feyerabend, Paul. Conquest of Abundance: A Tale of Abstraction
Versus the Richness of Being. Ed. Bert Terpstra. Chicago: U of
Chicago P, 1999.
Gross, Paul, and Norman Levitt. Higher Superstition: The Academic Left and its
Quarrels with Science. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1994.
Latour, Bruno. We Have Never Been Modern. Trans. Catherine
Porter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1993.
Lyotard, Jean-François. The Differend: Phrases in
Dispute. Trans. Georges
Van Den Abbeele. Minneapolis, MN: U of Minnesota P, 1988.
---. The Inhuman: Reflections on Time. Trans. Geoffrey
Bennington and
Rachel Bowlby. Stanford, CA: Stanford UP, 1991.
---. The Postmodern Condition. Trans. Geoffrey Bennington
and Brian
Massumi. Minneapolis, MN: U of Minnesota P, 1984.
Lyotard, Jean-François, and Jean-Loup Thêbaud. Just
Gaming. Trans. Brian
Massumi. Minneapolis, MN: U of Minnesota P, 1985.
Pielke, Roger A. Jr. "Science Policy: Policy, Politics, and Perspective."
Nature 416
(2002): 367-68.
Serres, Michel (with Bruno Latour). Conversations on Science, Culture,
and Time.
Trans. Roxanne Lapidus. Ann Arbor, MI: U of Michigan P, 1995.
Sokal, Alan, and Jean Bricmont. Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern
Intellectuals'
Abuse of Science. New York: Picador, 1998.
|