- I am grateful to Caleb Smith for his response to my essay "Stirner
and Foucault: Towards a Post-Kantian Freedom," and I particularly like
the way he links my discussion of a post-Kantian freedom to strategies of
resistance against contemporary forms of incarceration. Already, back in
the early 1970s, in response to a series of prison revolts in France,
Michel Foucault was talking about the emergence of a "carceral
archipelago"--a network of punitive institutions, discourses, and
practices that had been progressively spreading throughout the social
fabric since the late eighteenth century (297). It was as if the prison
had become a metaphor for society as a whole--with the same techniques of
surveillance and coercion appearing in schools, hospitals, factories, and
psychiatric institutions. Today, unprecedented technological developments
have made possible an intensification of social control to levels beyond
what even Foucault could have imagined--the proliferation, for instance,
of surveillance cameras in public spaces indicates a blurring of the
distinction between the institution and life outside. Indeed, in light of
the new forms of incarceration that are appearing today--the extra-legal
detention facilities in Guantanamo Bay, Cuba, for example--perhaps we
should take note of Giorgio Agamben's disturbing insight that what is
paradigmatic of modern life is not the prison, as Foucault believed, but
rather the camp (20). The slogan posted above the detention camp
at Guantanamo Bay--"Honor Bound to Defend Freedom"--is chillingly and
ironically reminiscent of another infamous slogan, the one posted above
Auschwitz: "Arbeit Macht Frei" ("Work Makes One Free").
-
Given this proliferation today of spaces of incarceration and
detention--which are, at the same time, becoming virtually indistinguishable
from everyday life--questions of freedom and emancipation, always central to
political discourse, are perhaps more crucial now than ever before. It is
here that Smith raises some very interesting questions about how Stirner's
and Foucault's emancipatory strategies might be useful today in challenging
contemporary institutions, and practices of incarceration, particularly
solitary confinement. As Smith shows, solitary confinement has been employed
as a punitive tool since the inception of the modern prison in the early nineteenth century, and
is now undergoing a massive resurgence in prisons in the U.S. It was
originally believed
that if prisoners were isolated within their own individual cells, not only
could
they be more easily controlled and supervised, but their very "souls" could
be redeemed through a process of self-reflection. Solitary confinement thus
served as a sort of moral experiment upon the subjectivity of the individual
inmate--an experiment in which the criminal's soul was constructed as a
discursive object to be corrected and reformed. A similar approach can be
seen in contemporary practices of solitary confinement in detention camps,
where the psyches of inmates are carefully monitored in an effort to unlock
their "secrets." Smith is right in suggesting, moreover, that this has become
a "postmodern" form of punishment--one that relies on sophisticated and
subtle techniques of psychological manipulation, rather than clumsy physical
coercion (though of course, as we have been amply reminded by events in Iraq,
the latter has by no means been expunged from contemporary carceral
practice).
-
However, the question remains as to what sort of strategies of freedom are
effective in resisting
these new postmodern regimes of punishment? Smith suggests that the
post-Kantian or "postmodern" notion of freedom that I have theorized in
my paper--one that is derived from the interventions of Foucault and
Stirner--is not only somewhat limited in resisting "concrete" practices
of incarceration, but, because it is based largely on a notion of
individual autonomy that may be achieved even within oppressive
conditions, may actually sustain these very practices. There are three
separate, yet related, points that Smith is making here:
firstly, that, despite my emphasis on concreteness and
particularity as opposed to abstract universals, I have to some extent
ignored concrete practices or institutions--like the prison--and have
thus remained within the very abstract world I am attacking;
secondly, that my attempt to theorize a notion of freedom and
individual autonomy--"ownness"--that can be realized even in conditions
of oppression is of limited use against the practice of solitary
confinement, and may even sustain it; and thirdly, that this
notion of individual autonomy, developed from Stirner and Foucault, has
ignored a very important dimension of their thinking that supports the
idea of collective insurgency--one that would be more relevant to the
question of prison revolt. I think Smith raises some very interesting
points here, and in answering his criticisms my aim is not simply to defend
my own argument but rather to expand the terms of the discussion so that it
may develop in new theoretical directions. In this
sense, I shall approach Smith's intervention in the spirit of
agonism, rather than antagonism--that is, as a theoretical
challenge that opens up new ways of thinking, new "lines of flight."
-
"Lines of flight" are exactly what we want here, after all. How to construct
new lines of flight, new strategies that will liberate people from
institutions like the prison, and, more broadly, from the
carceral/bio-political society we are living in today? Concrete practices
and institutions of coercion and surveillance are all around us--not just
in the prison, but, as I have suggested, at all levels of the social
network. Why, then, resurrect Max Stirner, the thinker who was obsessed
with ghosts, "spooks," and ideological apparitions, and who claimed that
we can be dominated and oppressed as much by an abstract idea as we can
by a "real" institution or social relation? How useful is Stirner's
critique of the abstract world of universal ideals--the spectres of
humanity, rationality, and morality--in combating very real practices and
institutions of domination? How is Stirner's diagnosis of a spectral
world relevant to a world that seems ever more frighteningly
real?
-
Many people, including, most famously, Marx, have suggested that because the
target of Stirner's critique is the abstract world of idealism, he neglects
the "real" material world of concrete relations and institutions. Indeed,
Marx and Engels devoted the largest part of The German Ideology
to attacking Stirner, accusing him of the worst kind of naïvety and
idealism. They repeatedly parody Stirner as "Saint Max" or "Saint Sancho"--as
one who mistakes illusions for reality. Stirner, Marx and Engels argue,
attempts to overcome religious alienation by condemning the dominance of
abstract "fixed ideas" but, in doing so, overestimates the importance of
these ideas in the real world, thus falling into the idealist trap himself.
In other words, Stirner, in focusing on the way that abstract ideas dominate
our lives, sees these ideas as all-determining, thus neglecting their basis
in real material and social conditions. Stirner is therefore characterized as
an ideologist par excellence--one who ignores the concrete material
world and conjures up instead a word of illusions and apparitions.
-
This idealist illusion is most apparent, Marx and Engels argue, in
Stirner's understanding of the State. Stirner sees the State as itself an
ideological abstraction, much like God--it only exists because we allow
it to exist, because we abdicate to it our own authority, in the same way
that we create God by abdicating our authority and placing it outside
ourselves. What is more important than the institution of the State is
the "ruling principle"--it is the idea of the State, in other
words, that dominates us (Stirner 200). The State's unity and dominance
exist mostly in the minds of its subjects. The State's power is really
based on our power, according to Stirner. It is only because the
individual has not recognized this power, because he humbles himself
before authority, that the State continues to exist. As Stirner correctly
surmised, the State cannot function only through top-down repression and
coercion, as this would expose its power in all its nakedness, brutality,
and illegitimacy. Rather, the State relies on our allowing it to
dominate us. Stirner wants to show that ideological apparatuses are not
only concerned with economic or political questions--they are also rooted
in psychological needs. The dominance of the State, Stirner suggests,
depends on our willingness to let it dominate us, on our complicit desire
for our own subordination. Therefore, the State must first be overcome as
an idea before it can be overcome in reality--or more precisely, they are
two sides of the same coin. According to Marx and Engels, however, this
ignores the economic and class relations that form the material basis of
the state: Stirner's "idealism" would absurdly allow the state to be
dismissed by an act of "wishful thinking" (374).
-
Now this critique of Stirner's "idealist" approach to the State goes to
the heart of the debate between me and Smith. Indeed, Smith's suggestion
that I, in my critique (via Stirner) of abstract universal ideals, fail
fully to acknowledge or account for the concreteness of institutions like
the prison, uncannily resembles Marx and Engels's attack on Stirner for
not recognizing the concreteness of institutions like the State. As
with the critique of Stirner, it is objected that my thinking in effect proposes
the existence of "abstract" prisons from which there can only be "abstract"
forms of escape. Like the unfortunate Saint Max, who stumbles foggily
through the world of illusions, I am said to be gesturing toward the
concrete world "as if toward something half-real." Now my response to
this is as follows: Smith's objection, which so closely parallels Marx
and Engels's materialist critique of Stirner, is itself based on a sort
of illusory separation between discourse and reality, in which "reality"
is privileged as "concrete" and as having an immediacy that ideas and
theoretical concepts do not. However, I would suggest here not only
that "concrete" objects and practices are meaningless outside discourse
(that is, the linguistic, symbolic, and ideological networks within which they are
constituted) but, more precisely, that these institutions and
practices themselves have a sort of spectral ideological dimension that
gives them consistency. In the same way, for instance, that Stirner
argues that the State cannot be understood, let alone resisted, without
an understanding of the abstract ideological systems that legitimize it,
I am suggesting that "concrete" institutions and practices cannot be
separated from the spectral ideological and symbolic systems that give
them meaning--and that, in order to resist these institutions and
practices, we have first to attack their spectral underside. For
instance, Foucault shows that the "abstract" concept of the
soul--which Smith himself has drawn upon--has very real material effects,
allowing a sort of discursive cage to be constructed for the prisoner: as
he expresses it in his famous inversion of the traditional formula, "the
soul is the prison of the body" (30).
-
What I am suggesting here is that, paradoxically, in order for us to
perceive what is concrete we must go through the abstract, or at least
the symbolic. That is to say, we can only grasp institutions and
practices in their concrete materiality through an "abstract" symbolic
and ideological framework which constitutes their meaning. They cannot be
seen as somehow outside or separate from this. As Slavoj Zizek argues,
there is nothing more ideological than the belief that we can
somehow step outside ideological systems and see things for the "way they
really are" (60). The world of abstract ideas and ideological systems does not
somehow stand apart from and opposed to the world of concrete, material practices and
institutions, as Smith seems to suggest; but rather, each can
only be articulated through the other. While it is true that I have not
referred in my paper directly to "concrete" institutions and practices,
my contention is that they can only be grasped through their spectral,
abstract, "half-real" dimension--and it is this dimension that I have
focused on in discussing Stirner's critique. It is a mistake to believe
that Stirner's critique of abstract universals implies that they can be
simply dismissed, and that a new world of reality and concreteness will
be revealed to us--it is more sophisticated than this. Just because this
world is spectral and ideological does not mean that it is not, at the
same time, very real--on the contrary, ideology is all around
us, materially present and deeply entrenched in our psyches. And what Stirner is interested in unmasking is the way that these abstract
ideals, such as morality, rationality, and human essence, find their
logical expression in concrete practices of domination--for instance, in
punishment, which Stirner sees as a form of moral hygiene (213). It is
precisely the abstract notions of morality and humanity that make this
new system of punishment intelligible--that form the ideological and
discursive apparatus that gives it meaning. That is why the State, for
Stirner, is as much ideological and spectral as it is "real." Indeed, it
is constituted in its materiality precisely through this abstract,
ideological dimension. This is what Marx and Engels did not
understand--and it could be argued here that in neglecting the State's
ideological dimension, and by reducing it to the "materiality" of
economic relations, they have themselves failed to grasp its
reality--that is, its political specificity and autonomy. To suggest, as
Smith seems to, that my focus on abstract structures of idealism has
obscured or neglected the real, material world, is simply to repeat
Marx's and Engel's error.
-
The second point that Smith makes is that Stirner's idea of "ownness" as
a form of radical freedom that is possible even in oppressive conditions
may actually contribute to the practice of solitary confinement. This is
because solitary confinement is based on the notion of a "cellular soul"
that can be self-correcting, and Stirner's notion of ownness,
though it seeks to throw off repressive moral constraints, nevertheless
sustains the idea of a soul that can be redeemed--this time in egoism
rather than morality. Smith raises an interesting point--that because the
egoist, for Stirner, creates his own forms of freedom, he can maintain a
Buddhist-like spiritual detachment from the real conditions of restraint
and coercion that he is subjected to, and that this may actually sustain,
or at any rate allow to be sustained, the practice of
incarceration in solitary
confinement. In other words, the implications of Stirner's theory of
ownness would seem to be that the egoist can be free even in a prison
cell. It is certainly the case that ownness is largely based on the
individual seizing for himself a radical autonomy through the rejection
of universal essences and fixed ideas. Moreover, Stirner does indeed say
that this form of autonomy can be experienced even in the most oppressive
conditions: "under the dominion of a cruel master my body is not 'free'
from torments and lashes; but it is my bones that moan under
the torture, my fibres that quiver under the blows [...]" (143).
What Stirner is suggesting here is that even in conditions of abject
slavery, in which the concept of freedom as an ideal becomes meaningless,
there is nevertheless a more immediate form of autonomy or
"self-ownership" available to the subject. Moreover, this internal
autonomy is something upon which the concrete act of resistance and
liberation can be based: the egoist, Stirner says, bides his time while
submitting to punishment, and "as I keep my eye on myself and my
selfishness, I take by the forelock the first good opportunity to trample
the slaveholder into the dust" (143). So what Stirner is trying to
develop here is similar to the notion of positive freedom--a form of
internal freedom or autonomy that goes beyond simple freedom
from external constraint. While it is usually the case that positive
freedom presupposes a basic negative freedom, in the case of
incarceration or slavery, there is no possibility of this prior condition
of negative freedom. Positive internal freedom must therefore form the a
priori condition for any act of resistance. An example of this strategy
of ownness in action might be found in the film Cool Hand
Luke. "Cool Hand" Luke, played by Paul Newman, is a convict on a
chain gang. In one scene the prisoners are building a road with picks and
shovels, and they are working at a slow, monotonous pace that is
regulated, not only by the enforced generalized boredom of the task, but
also by the watchful gaze of the guards. The prisoners are languidly
dreaming of their freedom, of life on the "outside." Luke suddenly urges
his fellow prisoners to intensify the pace of the digging, saying all
time "Go hard! Beat the Man!" The building of the road becomes a
frenetic collective activity that causes profound consternation amongst
the prison guards. Here we see the convicts taking a kind of
self-ownership over their activity, an activity from which they were
hitherto
alienated because it was seen as something that had to be done for
the authorities, for "the Man." By the convicts owning their own labor,
by making it theirs, it becomes an act of resistance.
-
Stirner is also making another, more subtle point here: as well as the
act of resistance being based on a radical internal freedom, the reverse
of this is that practices and institutions of domination actually rely on
an internalized oppression, whereby the subject is not only externally
coerced and incarcerated but is also tied, in more profound ways, to this
very identity of oppression. That is, institutions do not only oppress
and coerce the subject from the outside--they also dominate the subject
inwardly. In other words, they rely on an active
self-domination--the subject is tied psychologically to the very
institution that dominates him, and this might continue even after the
institution itself has disappeared. The subject is tied to a kind of
spectral shadow of the institution, precisely through an internalization
of the moral and rational norms upon which the institution is based. This
spectral shadow is precisely the hidden "authoritarian obverse" that I
have referred to. The State, for instance, relies on certain forms of
subjectification, so that the individual comes to willingly submit
himself to its authority--so that, in the words of Stirner, "its
permanence is to be sacred to me" (161). So, for Stirner, any concrete
liberation from the institution must begin with a sort of
self-liberation--a liberation of the self from the forms of subjectivity
that are tied to the institution. This is what Stirner means by
"ownness." My point is, therefore, that Stirner's theory of
ownness--although it would seem to mirror, as Smith suggests, a fantasy
of "corrective solitude"--can actually be interpreted in another, much
more radical way. It can be seen as a way of overcoming the forms of
self-domination and servitude upon which practices of incarceration are
ultimately based.
-
Although any act of liberation must begin with a personal individual
liberation, it will ultimately be ineffective unless it incorporates a
collective dimension--and it is here that I am inclined to agree with
Smith in his emphasis on collective insurgency. I believe that notions of
collective action and identity are very much implicit in both Stirner's
and Foucault's politics, despite the way that they are usually perceived
as valorizing only individual acts of resistance. Elsewhere I have
insisted on a collective dimension in their thought, drawing on Stirner's
important notion of the "union of egoists," as well as Foucault's
writings on the Iranian Revolution (Newman). As Smith points out, Stirner
himself talks about the way that the prison system, although designed to
isolate individuals, actually creates the conditions for a new kind of
collective intercourse and identity--one that constitutes a significant
threat to the prison system. So while in my article I have focused on the
individual--both in terms of the effect of abstract ideals and
ideological systems on the individual, as well as on different forms of
individual autonomy and resistance--there is no doubt that, for Stirner
at least, this can form the basis for a collective insurgency. There is
certainly nothing in either what I have said, or what Stirner and
Foucault have said, that rules this out. How else can we hope to
challenge the systems of power, surveillance, and domination in which we
are all increasingly being inscribed?
Department of Political Science
University of Western Australia
snewman@cyllene.uwa.edu.au
COPYRIGHT (c) 2004 Saul Newman. READERS MAY USE
PORTIONS OF THIS WORK IN ACCORDANCE WITH THE FAIR USE PROVISIONS OF U.S.
COPYRIGHT LAW. IN ADDITION, SUBSCRIBERS AND MEMBERS OF SUBSCRIBED
INSTITUTIONS MAY
USE THE ENTIRE WORK FOR ANY INTERNAL NONCOMMERCIAL PURPOSE BUT, OTHER THAN
ONE COPY SENT BY EMAIL, PRINT OR FAX TO ONE PERSON AT ANOTHER LOCATION FOR
THAT INDIVIDUAL'S PERSONAL USE, DISTRIBUTION OF THIS ARTICLE OUTSIDE OF A
SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION FROM EITHER THE
AUTHOR OR THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS IS EXPRESSLY FORBIDDEN.
THIS ARTICLE AND OTHER CONTENTS OF THIS ISSUE ARE
AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE UNTIL RELEASE OF THE NEXT ISSUE. A
TEXT-ONLY ARCHIVE OF THE JOURNAL IS ALSO AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE.
FOR FULL HYPERTEXT ACCESS TO BACK ISSUES, SEARCH UTILITIES, AND OTHER
VALUABLE FEATURES, YOU OR YOUR INSTITUTION MAY SUBSCRIBE TO
PROJECT MUSE, THE
ON-LINE JOURNALS PROJECT OF THE
JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS.
Works Cited
Agamben, Giorgio. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life.
Trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford UP, 1998.
Foucault, Michel. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the
Prison. Trans. Alan Sheridan. London: Penguin, 1991.
Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. The German Ideology. Collected
Works Vol. 5. New York: International; London: Lawrence & Wishart; Moscow: Progress,
1976.
Newman, Saul. "For Collective Social Action: Towards a Postmodern Theory
of Collective Identity." Philosophy and Social Action 27.1
(2001): 37-47.
Stirner, Max. The Ego and Its Own. Ed. David Leopold.
Cambridge: Cambridge UP: 1995.
Zizek, Slavoj. "The Spectre of Ideology." The Zizek Reader.
Ed. Elizabeth Wright and Edmond Wright. Oxford: Blackwell, 1999. 55-86.
|