Review of:
David W. Bernstein and Christopher Hatch, eds., Writings through
John Cage's Music, Poetry, and Art. Chicago: U
of Chicago P, 2001.
-
Agree or disagree with his aesthetics, his ideas, or his politics, no one
seriously engaged in studying the arts of the twentieth century can
afford to ignore John Cage or his wide-ranging body of work. His
influence on experimental forms of music is well documented, but his
achievements and influence in the fields of literature, visual arts, and
film are also significant and worthy of more discussion. Writings
through John Cage's Music, Poetry, and Art, edited by David W.
Bernstein and Christopher Hatch, is an attempt, as Bernstein states in
his introduction, to "give readers a sense of the importance of Cage's
creative activities in a variety of fields and an understanding of how
much research has yet to be done" (6). It is both the book's greatest
achievement and most significant failure that it accomplishes both of
these aims.
- The book is an extension of the "Here Comes Everybody:
The Music, Poetry, and Art of John Cage" conference, which took place at
Mills College in Oakland, California in the autumn of 1995, and so "was
the first international assemblage of scholars and creative artists to
examine Cage's work after his death on August 12, 1992" (1); indeed, the
idea for the conference developed less than a year after Cage's death
(ix). This link between Cage's death and the conference is carried over
in the essays included in Writings, as almost all of the
authors implicitly focus on the absence of John Cage, the man, either
through intricately describing his working practices, relating
personal anecdotes about Cage, describing what Cage meant to them
and their work, or, sometimes, by mixing all three of these
perspectives. For this reason, the book becomes a celebration of John
Cage's life and his art. Perhaps due to the short time that passed
between Cage's death and the germination of this project, the book is,
for the most part, more of a wake for a great man than a critical
examination of Cage's works
- This is not to say that there isn't useful information in
the book; each essay offers interesting facts about Cage's creative
process, the performance of his work, and the scoring of his work. The
problem is that there is often a lack of critical examination of many of
these facts. The result is that the essays in the book could be
divided into two distinct types: those offering ideological critiques of
Cage's work and those documenting Cage's formal procedures. The former
engage intellectually with Cage's aesthetics, his beliefs, and his
politics and seek to open up ways to engage Cage's work critically; they
offer important insights into how Cage's personal beliefs, such as his
devotion to Zen, chance, and political and social anarchy, both affected his work and offer insights into the works themselves. The second type
of essays, those documenting Cage's creative process, generally avoids
issues of ideology in an attempt to describe objectively how Cage created
his works. These essays, it seems to me, are less valuable, precisely
because they refuse to deal with the issues that Cage found so important
in life and art; they focus on Cage, not on his works, and so they fail
to open up avenues of investigation into Cage's music, visual art, or
literary texts.
- The book starts quite strongly. The first essay, by
David W. Bernstein, examines Cage's music in relation to the large
umbrella terms "avant-garde," "modernism," and "postmodernism."
Bernstein offers a nuanced investigation of Cage's art and his politics
in order to highlight both the experimental as well as the traditional
aspects of Cage's music. Bernstein argues against the unexamined
conflation of experimentation with postmodernism and tradition with
modernism, instead showing how Cage exemplified aspects of both those
terms. By drawing on the influence that the early avant-garde,
especially dadaism but also futurism, had on Cage, Bernstein argues
persuasively that Cage's chance-based musical works do indeed have a
distinct political agenda:
when considering Cage's compositional methods, one finds that the
postmodern and the modern coexist without contradiction. The same is
true of Cage's political and social agenda. Through his redefinition of
musical form Cage created works modeling desirable political and social
structures. He was able to renew the modernist project dedicated to
political and social change through art using postmodernist artistic
techniques. As we assess Cage's role within the development of
twentieth-century thought and musical style and intensify the critical
evaluation of his creative output, it is crucial that we consider both
the traditional and the radical aspects of his aesthetics and
compositional style. This formidable task may very well occupy scholars
for many years to come. (40)
The essay refuses to categorize Cage within the unproductive binaries
that Cage himself constantly railed against; the result is an
appreciation of the complex balancing job Cage performed as a political
artist who avoided politics in his art and as a man who respected earlier
traditions at the same time that he worked to dismantle their
influences. Bernstein addresses the interplay between Cage's political
anarchy and his use of chance operations, and, more importantly, he
historicizes Cage within a continuum. Cage, Bernstein argues, openly
borrowed from earlier avant-garde movements while he also updated their
methods; he remained committed to the modernist avant-garde's belief in
social improvement through art, but refocused artistic practice around an
anarchistic refusal to engage in oppositional politics.
- Jonathan D. Katz, in the essay that follows Bernstein's,
expands on Cage's political beliefs and strategies while refocusing the
area of investigation onto and through Cage's closeted homosexuality.
Katz proposes that Cage's silence over his own sexuality strengthened his
interest both in the use of silence in music and in Eastern philosophies
such as Zen, which stress the positive aspects of silence. Biographical
criticism is a dangerous method to use when dealing with an artist like
Cage, who attempted to remove as much of his personality from his work as
he could, but Katz offers a convincing argument as to why he believes
this approach is appropriate: "there is a substantial difference between
saying that the work is not about the life (antiexpressionism) and saying
that the life has nothing to do with the work. There are, after all,
modes of revelation of self that have nothing to do with expressionism"
(47). Here Katz distinguishes between conventional biographical
criticism, which uses the artist's life to explain the meaning of a work
of art, and a criticism that acknowledges the importance of biography to
the interests and predispositions from which an artist will draw when
producing art. Katz deftly uses Cage's homosexuality, or more
specifically his refusal to acknowledge his homosexuality, as the primary
reason for Cage's use of silence in his works. From this
starting point, Cage became increasingly interested in Zen's belief that
silence was necessary to inner harmony, since "Zen repositioned the
closet, not as a source of repression or anxiety, but as a means to
achieve healing; it was in not talking about--and hence not
reifying--one's troubles that healing began" (45). Katz also points out
the revolutionary nature of Cage's use of silence,
considering that the use of silence was developed during the height of
public popularity for abstract expressionism, an art movement that
concentrated on creating grand Romantic myths about artists such as
Jackson Pollock and Robert Motherwell. But perhaps most importantly,
Katz draws a parallel between Cage's silence and his political beliefs.
Like Bernstein, Katz argues that Cage's art was implicitly political; for
Katz, silence provided Cage with a way to critique society's values
without engaging in oppositional politics, something that Cage believed
only perpetuated what was supposedly being argued against:
silence was much more than conventionally unmusical; it provided a
route toward an active challenge of the assumptions and prejudices that
gave rise to homophobic oppression in the first place. For Cage, silence
was an ideal form of resistance, carefully attuned to the requirements of
the cold war consensus, at least in its originary social-historical
context. There are both surrender and resistance in these silences, in
relation not of either/or but of both/and[...]. That Cage's
self-silencing was in keeping with the requirements of the infamously
homophobic McCarthy era should not obscure the fact that it was also
internally and ideologically consistent with his larger aesthetic
politics. (53-4)
While Katz's essay does not deal with all of the political aspects of
Cage's work (for example, an analysis of Cage's commitment to political
anarchism would have been interesting in this context), Katz effectively
brings to the forefront the often-overlooked political aspects of Cage's
work.
- Austin Clarkson's essay, "The Intent of the Musical
Moment: Cage and the Transpersonal," offers interesting insights into how
Cage's music was presentational, not representational. Presentational
arts, Clarkson argues, create their own codes of meaning as they are
expressed, while representational arts rely on a prior understanding of
the codes by both the artist and the recipients. For this reason,
Clarkson argues that Cage was not avant-garde; the avant-gardists still
believed their art to be representational, since they "took their works
to be fully realized creations and not experiments in the sense of trials
or tests" (66). Clarkson's emphasis on the creative role of the audience
in the presentational arts, a belief that Cage held, is an important
point, and it might allow Clarkson to draw connections between Cage's
music and other contemporary fields that share this belief, such as
L=A=N=G=U=A=G=E poetry (or even Cage's own poetry). However, Clarkson
does not draw these connections and remains somewhat narrowly focused on
the world of music. Moreover, Clarkson's assertion that Cage was purely
an experimental artist and not an avant-gardist reinforces the strict and
rather unhelpful divisions between aesthetic camps, divisions that all of
Cage's mature work attempted to undercut. Unlike Bernstein and Katz, who
work to show how these boundaries are far more fluid than critics would
admit, Clarkson mans the barricades. For example, Clarkson does not
address the fact that the conflation between art and life that he states
lies at the heart of presentational art also forms the core of the
historical avant-garde movements.[1]
Moreover, he also overlooks the connection between Cage's political and
social anarchy and his desire to make the audience part of the creative
element of the work. Still, despite these drawbacks, Clarkson's focus on
the creative relationship called for by presentational art is an
important point, especially since he stresses that both the audience and
the artist must learn to adapt to these new roles.
- Bernstein's, Katz's, and Clarkson's essays are
particularly illuminating because they demonstrate that an awareness of
Cage's aesthetic and political beliefs adds to the levels of possible
meaning in all of Cage's post-1950 work. These writers focus on
explaining and expanding possible nuances in the works through a
knowledge of Cage's personal beliefs. However, most of the remaining
essays abandon this practice of theorizing levels of meaning in Cage's
oeuvre in favor of merely describing Cage's compositional processes. The
result is that, while useful facts are offered, there are very few
moments of true critical insight into Cage's aesthetics or his works in
the bulk of the book.
- In the essay "Cage as Performer," Gordon Mumma offers an
interesting but standard brief biography of Cage as a performer. Deborah
Campana, in "As Time Passes," discusses how time remained central to
Cage's compositional strategies throughout his different musical periods,
but she offers no ideas about why this was so or what light it might shed
on his work. In "David Tudor and the Solo for Piano," John Holzapfel
discusses Tudor's active role in interpreting Cage's music, stressing the
collaborative nature of their relationship but offers no thoughts on how
this affects Cage's music. Jackson Mac Low offers a necessarily brief
and admittedly limited discussion of Cage's writings in "Cage's Writings
up to the Late 1980s." Mac Low argues that Cage never sought to expunge
personal decisions from his writings, but the broad overview that Mac Low
offers doesn't allow for in-depth analysis.
- The collection also includes the transcripts from two
panel discussions at the "Here Comes Everybody" conference. The panel on
"Cage's Influence" was composed of Gordon Mumma (chair), Allan Kaprow,
James Tenney, Christian Wolff, Alvin Curram, and Maryanne Amasher. More
so than most of the pieces included, this discussion is openly laudatory
of Cage; it offers few insights and serves more as a chance for those
involved to thank Cage publicly for opening avenues of investigation that
allowed them to form their careers. In fact, they all agree that Cage's
influence was more indirect, through his role as a trailblazer, than
direct. The second panel discussion, "Cage and the Computer," offers
more insight, but in terms of detailing Cage's compositional practices
rather than advancing any theoretical insights into the importance of the
computer to Cage. Composed of James Pritchett (chair), James Tenney,
Frances White, and Andrew Culver (Cage's long-serving computer
assistant), the panel describes how early work with computers developed,
but mostly this piece is interesting for Culver's anecdotes about how
Cage worked with the computer: he didn't. Culver did all of the computer
work himself, finding out what Cage wanted and then making it happen.
- Henning Lohner's discussion of "The Making of Cage's
One" closes the book. It is an interesting blend of
interview, personal anecdote, documentation, and critical discussion on
the topic of Lohner's collaboration with Cage on the experimental film
One (Cage's last major work). The piece serves as a
biography of the collaboration, an elegy (Cage died after the film was
completed but before it was premiered), and as a witness to Cage's
compositional strategies. Moreover, it is a fractured piece of writing,
paratactically juxtaposing interviews with Cage, documentation
surrounding the film, anecdotes of working with Cage, and thoughts on the
medium of film. As such, it is the only non-linear piece of writing in
the book (Clarkson does attempt something different in his essay, where
he includes a series of quotes from Cage after his essay, but that essay
is straightforward in terms of structure). This point leads me to one of
the major drawbacks of this collection: there is too much similarity and
consensus among the writers and essays included.
- Considering the short time-span between Cage's death and
the germination of the conference from which this book sprang, it is
hardly surprising that the essayists came together to praise Cage, not to
bury him. However, considering Cage's incessant search for
experimentation in all of his artistic endeavors, it seems a poor tribute
to him to ignore the practices and aesthetics that he worked so hard to
establish. Cage, for example, was a noted anarchist (a fact rarely
addressed or even acknowledged in most of the essays); part of his desire
to do away with the conventional structures of music, language, and the
visual arts sprang directly from his belief that these structures upheld
conventional opinions about society, opinions that Cage certainly did not
share. For example, Cage often stated his preference for "nonsyntaxed"
language: "Due to N. O. Brown's remark that syntax is the arrangement of
the army, and Thoreau's that when he heard a sentence he heard feet
marching, I became devoted to nonsytactical 'demilitarized' language"
(Introduction). The connection between doing away with the accepted
codes of language and critiquing the status quo is obvious in Cage's
statement; for the authors in the book to undertake such standard
investigations of Cage and his work is to turn away from his implicit
critiques of logical communication and stifle these critiques under the
weight of convention. Moreover, Cage constantly and often proudly
contradicted himself; this was not merely an attempt to be difficult or
inscrutable (both ideas were tied in Cage's mind with the Romantic myth
of the artist, and were to be avoided at all cost).[2] Cage's contradictions came from his distrust of
consensus (a point which only Bernstein and Katz make), a distrust that
arose partly from his belief in anarchy (which holds that reifications of
any type, even personal characteristics, should be avoided in favor of
openness to circumstances), and partly from his interest in Zen (which
states that logic is not the only way, or indeed the best way to
understand the world). It would be a far greater tribute to Cage and his
work if his critics here openly debated the ideas, importance, and merit
of Cage's work. As he so often stated, Cage was not interested in
creating art, which in his mind was dead and reified; however, the consistently laudatory tone of the
essays implicitly moves Cage's works toward that category, toward
installing him as another Great Artist within the canon.[3]
- Perhaps the greatest drawback to the collection, though,
can be illustrated in relation to the two essays not yet discusssed:
Constance Lewallen's "Cage and the Structure of Chance" and Ray Kass's
"Diary: Cage's Mountain Lake Workshop, April 8-15, 1990."
Coincidentally, both of these essays address Cage's visual works; this,
however, isn't the problem. Both Lewallen and Kass attempt to detail
Cage's creative process, and it is this attempt that leads to the
problem: both essays focus on Cage, the man as artist, and, as such, both
essays undercut Cage's attempt to divorce his own ego from his work.
Indeed, neither Lewallen nor Kass deal critically with Cage's works at
all. Instead, they focus on Cage's creative process in minute detail,
cataloging his every decision. The result is that, although Cage does
appear to be rather idiosyncratic, he is once again reshaped in the
critics' minds as a Great Artist. For example, note the laudatory tone
and the emphasis on Cage the Artist (not on the works that Cage happened
to produce) in the following:
Cage managed to challenge just about all of Western culture's
received ideas about what art is. If, from the Renaissance on, art has
been regarded as a means of communication, Cage instead defined art as
self-alteration, a means to "sober the mind." If art has served to give
form to the chaos of life's experiences, he created an art that as nearly
as possible combines with, rather than gives shape to, life. If art has
been regarded as a giver of truths through the "self-expressed
individuality of artist," Cage saw it rather as an exploration of how
nature itself functions as a means to open the mind and spirit to the
beauty of life with a minimum of artistic expression or
interpenetration. Finally, if art has traditionally expressed meaning
through symbol or metaphor, he preferred that viewers provide their own
meaning according to their individual personality and experience.
(Lewallen 242-3)
One can't help but feel that no matter what "art has been regarded as,"
for Lewallen, Cage would have heroically challenged it. I don't mean to
downplay Cage's sense of experimentation, but the Romantic myth of the
artist is strikingly apparent in both Lewallen's and Kass's pieces (and
runs implicitly through most of the other essays). Lewallen refuses to
contextualize Cage, and thus there is no sense of how Cage learned from
others (Suzuki, Fuller, Thoreau, Kropotkin, etc.) the challenges that he
put into place. This decontextualization fuels the transformation of
Cage from experimenter in the arts into one of the reified,
understandable Artists of the Canon by writing the narrative of Cage's
life and artistic achievements within the frame of the grand, solitary,
creative genius. Not only does this transformation violate Cage's
beliefs, but it also serves to tame his challenges, which become
recuperated within the framework of Art (Peter Bürger and Paul Mann,
for example, both describe how the art world recuperated the challenges
against the institution of art made by the avant-garde movements by first
claiming these challenges as art). Furthermore, Cage's works
are themselves overlooked in an attempt to install him firmly within the
tradition of artistic revolution, a type of artistic anti-tradition that
in every way deeply depends on what it supposedly is trying to undermine.
- In the end, what a book like Writings through John
Cage's Music, Poetry, and Art does is to display the conservatism
of most criticism of experimental art. Despite the constant challenges
offered by artists in all of the different media--challenges which Cage
in many ways helped to nurture and perpetuate--critics refuse to adapt
either the form or the content of their discussions. As such, the
critics play a front-line role in recuperating experimental art and
artists such as John Cage. Having said that, I'm not entirely sure how
to avoid playing this role; however, we might learn from the example of
the experimental artists themselves and break down the conventions of
academic criticism. If Cage taught us nothing else, it is that there are
ways outside of conventional logic to understand the world and all things
in it; perhaps, then, it is time for critics at least to gesture toward
the idea that conventional logic is not necessarily the most appropriate
nor the only way to engage with experimental art.
- Writings through John Cage's Music, Poetry, and
Art could serve as a useful introduction to John Cage's work,
especially in the field of music. It contains many useful facts about
his working process; however, this raw data is not examined effectively
by the essayists included in this book. Aside from the first three
essays and a few of the later ones, there is little here that will
significantly expand the way readers might encounter John Cage's works.
What the book points to is the divide in Cage studies between those
critics offering ideological critiques of his works, critiques which
actively engage with the ideas and beliefs that Cage brought to his
works, and those who focus on Cage himself. In the end,
Writings shows that the focus must shift from the latter to
the former if studies of Cage are going to increase the critical
appreciation of John Cage's music, poetry, and art.
Department of English
University of Alberta
aweaver@ualberta.ca
COPYRIGHT (c) 2004 BY Andy Weaver.
READERS MAY USE PORTIONS
OF THIS WORK IN ACCORDANCE WITH THE FAIR USE PROVISIONS OF U.S. COPYRIGHT
LAW. IN ADDITION, SUBSCRIBERS AND MEMBERS OF SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTIONS MAY
USE THE ENTIRE WORK FOR ANY INTERNAL NONCOMMERCIAL PURPOSE BUT, OTHER THAN
ONE COPY SENT BY EMAIL, PRINT OR FAX TO ONE PERSON AT ANOTHER LOCATION FOR
THAT INDIVIDUAL'S PERSONAL USE, DISTRIBUTION OF THIS ARTICLE OUTSIDE OF A
SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION FROM EITHER THE
AUTHOR OR THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS IS EXPRESSLY FORBIDDEN.
THIS ARTICLE AND OTHER CONTENTS OF THIS ISSUE ARE
AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE UNTIL RELEASE OF THE NEXT ISSUE. A
TEXT-ONLY ARCHIVE OF THE JOURNAL IS ALSO AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE. FOR
FULL HYPERTEXT ACCESS TO BACK ISSUES, SEARCH UTILITIES, AND OTHER VALUABLE
FEATURES, YOU OR YOUR INSTITUTION MAY SUBSCRIBE TO
PROJECT MUSE, THE
ON-LINE JOURNALS PROJECT OF THE JOHNS
HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS.
Notes
1. Peter Bürger, for example, sees
the conflation of art and life as one of the fundamental tenets of the
early avant-garde. In Theory of the Avant-Garde, he states
that "the European avant-garde movements can be defined as an attack on
the status of art in bourgeois society. What is negated is not an
earlier form of art (a style) but art as an institution that is
unassociated with the life praxis of men" (49).
2. Take, for example, this exchange
between Richard Kostelanetz and Cage in Kostelanetz's Conversing
With Cage:
[Kostelanetz] Once someone asked you a very dull question, trying to show
that you had been inconsistent in a line of reasoning, and I remember
that with that marvelous laugh of yours you said, 'Well, you won't find
me consistent.'
[Cage] Emerson felt this way about consistency, you know; but our
education leads us to think that it's wrong to be inconsistent. All
consistency is, really, is getting one idea and not deviating from it,
even if the circumstances change so radically that one ought to deviate
[...]. (45)
3. Cage made it clear that he did not
want to create art, which, like the dadaists, he saw as cut-off from
life:
I RATHER THINK THAT CONTEMPORARY MUSIC WOULD BE THERE IN THE DARK TOO,
BUMPING INTO THINGS, KNOCKING OTHERS OVER AND IN GENERAL ADDING TO THE
DISORDER THAT CHARACTERIZES LIFE (IF IT IS OPPOSED TO ART) RATHER THAN
ADDING TO THE ORDER AND STABILIZED TRUTH BEAUTY AND POWER THAT
CHARACTERIZE A MASTERPIECE (IF IT IS OPPOSED TO LIFE). AND IS IT? YES
IT IS. (Silence 46)
Works
Cited
Bürger, Peter. Theory of the Avant-Garde. Trans.
Michael Shaw. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1984.
Cage, John. Introduction. Writing Through Finnegans Wake.
Spec. supplement to James Joyce Quarterly. Vol. 15, U of
Tulsa Monograph Ser. 16. N.p.: n.p., 1978.
---. Silence. Hanover: Wesleyan UP, 1973.
Kostelanetz, Richard. Conversing With Cage. New York:
Limelight, 1988.
|