Review of:
Tabbi, Joseph, Cognitive Fictions. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2002.
- Cognitive Fictions is a sophisticated and fascinating book that asks difficult questions
about
the place of literature and the literary artist in the age of digitized mass media. The answers Joseph Tabbi provides are
equally difficult, although the reader's trouble on this score will depend in part on whether or not he or she ascribes to some
of the guiding assumptions that motivate the inquiry. To its credit, this is a book that provokes an
emotional response. However, Tabbi's reliance on the modular theory of
mind (more on this later) elicits considerable discomfort even for a reader
who does not consider himself or herself a traditional humanist.
- But first things first: Cognitive Fictions represents an important
contribution to U.S. literary studies. Tabbi rightly insists that in a global culture
literary studies must engage more with science and with media studies. Taking issue with what he sees as a
predominantly unmediated
situation of literature studies in its geopolitical framework, Tabbi suggests another approach: we must develop closer and more
detailed "connections with the sciences and with those communications media whose recent expansion and unprecedented
integration into everyday life made a global culture possible . . . in the first place" (xviii). Thus, if the novel is to
continue to possess a recognizable cultural diversity and historical specificity, and if we are to continue to respect it for
such differences, then "it first needs to define itself within and against those more globalizing powers and distribution
networks that threaten to erase the novel's medial difference" (xix).
- This is the task that Tabbi has set for himself. In a time when all forms of
communication (image, sound,
text) can be digitized, and at a point in cultural history when irony, once the hallmark of the postmodern
literary, has been wholly
subsumed by advertising culture, he asks along with the small group of U.S. writers he investigates: What is the novel for?
What does it do? Why does our culture continue to produce and consume works of fiction? For Tabbi, the contemporary
novelist's purpose has nothing to do with nostalgia for the Real; it is not about the recovery of an
"authentic" America, because in a world where electronic mass media has penetrated so deeply into the collective consciousness
that distinction no longer has any value, if it ever did. The purpose of the fiction writer is rather to re-purpose or
re-mediate the complex social/communications systems within which our minds and bodies are enmeshed through the processes of
observation, or rather, observation of observation.
- Tabbi's inspiration here is the autopoesis of Maturana and Varela, and the work of Niklas
Luhmann as well. Just
as "autopoesis describes a way of establishing and maintaining a system's boundary by selecting meaningful elements
(distinctions the system can use) out of an otherwise indistinct, 'noisy,'
environment" (xxii-xxiii), the writers that Tabbi
examines (at least in the latter portion of his book) obsessively observe and take notes in journalistic fashion, or rather
their protagonists do. Such close observation of the social systems that constitute them makes (or marks) a difference that
becomes useable as a platform for fresh insight about those systems. Tabbi explains:
In recognizing the absolute closure of the system . . . , these narrators create a new distinction, which then enters into the
system it describes and alters it. So the moment a narrator recognizes the possibility of keeping a "journal of the journal,"
or turning one's isolated inconsequential notations into an "absolutely autobiographical novel," the narrator can re-enter the
system at another level (and at a later time), and thus keep things
going. The distinction (analogous to what cognitive science
would term a "gap" and literary theory might call the "aporia") between rhetoric and meaning, the writer/observer and the
writing/system under observation, is no longer a distinction between inside and outside. Rather, by imagining oneself as
"outside," the observer introduces a new distinction within the writing-system. Hence the possibility of moving the system
(not necessarily "up") to a different level of complexity, so that it can function differently within the environment (because
it is now structurally capable of making new distinctions and hence seeing things within the environment that were not visible
before). (xxii)
- Here Tabbi urges that we must distinguish between autopoesis and an autotelic theory of
the literary that insists upon the absolute isolation of the literary work from the hum of background
noise. Autopoetic art encloses itself in and as a
world of words, but it does so in relation to the outside. The distinction between the autopoetic and the
autotelic is critical for Tabbi, given his desire to save for the literary artist a purpose or a value
that the self-reflexive modernist lost in a hall of mirrors no longer offers us. Writers such as
Paul Auster in his New York Trilogy, David Markson in Wittgenstein's Mistress,
and Harry Matthews in The Journalist are not out of touch, and they certainly don't go about
conjuring a world elsewhere in the New Critical sense. But then the real issue for Tabbi is what it means to be in touch, and how one goes about mediating reality (as a novelist) in a world where
human perception is already so profoundly mediated: "Reflexivity in contemporary fiction, like autopoetic
closure in cognitive science and in systems theory, is not a shutting out of the world," Tabbi insists.
"[I]t is rather a way of establishing an identity that is better able to connect with the world at
particular points, when one is able, while writing, to re-cognize and put on hold one's own literary
distinctions and categories long enough to see how they might answer to distinctions in the environment"
(80).
- The application of systems theory to literary study is promising, and it is likely that Tabbi's
project will prove inspirational for many readers and critics. Nevertheless, the difference between the autotelic and
the autopoetic is often quite difficult to grasp in Tabbi's readings; which is to say that it is hard to tell what practical
value his authors and/or their protagonists get out of the close observations that constitute their textual
interventions. Perhaps this is inevitable, given that Tabbi's concern is with states of consciousness, which are of course
rather ineffable stuff. Nevertheless, one is left with the distinctly unsettling impression that on Tabbi's account we are in
a world so utterly homogenized through mediation that there is no space for resistance. That is not
because of his use of
systems theory. If the fundamental lesson of systems theory is that human cognition is a moving blind spot, then as a theoretical framework within which to understand behavior, systems theory converges in some significant ways with other theoretical frameworks that trouble but do no obviate the value of talking about cultural resistance, such as the
psychoanalytical. Blind spots are one thing, but Tabbi's mobilization of the cognitive scientific model of mind represents
in itself a discrete aspect of his theoretical strategy, and we must separate this out from systems theory.
- My main grouse with Cognitive Fictions has to do with Tabbi's uncritical acceptance of what is
known as the modular theory of mind, the idea that the mind/brain is made up of systems whose resources
are site-specific, so
to speak, or "encapsulated" with respect to the data that each contains. According to this theory,
information in the brain is
stored in independent modules which have either very limited or no knowledge of what goes on outside, in surrounding domains.
But as Jerry Fodor has most vigorously argued in recent books, while the modular theory may indeed get the architecture of
local mental states right--those that pertain to beliefs, desires, and other forms of thought that can be
expressed
propositionally--it explains nothing about global, or conscious, states. Fodor writes in The Mind
Doesn't Work That Way:
Since the mental processes thus afflicted with globality apparently include some of the ones that are most characteristic of
human cognition, I'm on balance not inclined to celebrate how much we have so far learned about how our minds work. The bottom
line will be that the current situation in cognitive science is light years from being satisfactory. (5)
- Without getting into the considerable complexities of Fodor's arguments, which in any case pertain mainly to
the logical and empirical misgivings he has about the modularity thesis, suffice it to say that Fodor sees far greater virtue
in blending domain-specific and domain-general cognitive architectures. For if the mind is entirely modular, as cognitive
science is wont to argue; if "there is a more or less encapsulated processor for each kind of problem that
it can solve"; and
if "there is nothing in the mind that can ask questions about which solution to a problem is 'best overall,' that is, best in
light of the totality of a creature's beliefs and utilities," then for Fodor cognitive science has not
gotten us very far
in the study of human consciousness (64). This assertion on its own is a powder keg, and I do not want to
endorse it so much as to use
it to point toward a problem that dogs Cognitive Fictions on another level.
- Following McLuhan, Tabbi assumes from the start that our electronic media are extensions of
the human sensorium; in effect his book is a complex and sophisticated study of the relation between
those media on the one
hand and "the human measure" on the other. Whereas McLuhan in the sixties believed he confronted, as Mark Hansen puts it, "'a
situation in which the prostheses we adopt to cognize and intervene in the technologically driven material complexification of
the universe only seem to expand our experiential alienation'" (x), Tabbi re-envisions the relation between human beings and
their electronic prostheses, or their media environments, based on the discoveries of cognitive science. His next assumption,
and it is the value rather than the accuracy of this one that I question, is that the findings of cognitive
science refute
McLuhan's thesis that there is a poor fit between our media and our psychical economies. Digital
information processors do of course work
on the architectural principle of modularity. But instead of accepting neutrally that "emerging sciences of the
mind have produced detailed descriptions of similarly communicating agents, modules, and distributed networks in us"
(x), Tabbi could have more fully questioned from the start the motivations that have produced these discoveries, which are in
effect metaphorical associations. In other words, what Cognitive Fictions lacks is a substantial rhetorical
analysis of its cognitive science, because it is by no means a necessary correlative of systems
theory. Neither is it necessarily a good fit.
- Tabbi's decision to foreground systems theory and to
background the cognitive theory has a practical payoff
because it is a relatively safer critical strategy. It is even likely that it was the right decision, given that it frees him
to pursue systems-theoretical insights rigorously. We should not be
surprised, however,
that it produces a big blind spot. For Tabbi fails to see the trouble into which his under-theorized
articulation of
cognitive science with systems theory gets him right from the start, even in spite of his explicit statement of the
problem. Here is the statement, which refers back to the prior announcement of the modularity thesis: "With the coming
together of these two systems--call them the mind and the medial ecology--prospects for achieving a critical distance, never
hopeful in a postmodern context, seem increasingly unlikely" (x). True enough. But
the prospects for achieving the kind
of distance from our media ecology that would allow for truly productive critical inquiry into its
conditions and effects, which
is what Tabbi seems at least wistfully to hope for in this passage, are radically undermined precisely by the uncritical
acceptance of the modularity thesis. If we do not assume that the
mind is "coming together" with media systems by virtue of
deep structural affinities, then we will invariably find ourselves talking about some other kind of interface between them--one
perhaps, with more friction at work; and one, perhaps, where there is a greater possibility of achieving a
productive critical
distance from media forces. Tabbi is not entirely unaware of the problem. In fact he acknowledges it head on in his chapter
on Pynchon and cognitive science:
For a humanism that wishes to read signs of community in a multi-voiced and multicultural past, the implications [of
modularity] remain disturbing: when consciousness, like corporate power, is itself composed of a collection of partially
connected modules or media, what resistance is possible? .... Just as cognitive theories
of the modular mind require no self, the
proliferating connections among voices and identities in Pynchon's two most recent novels require no community. (52)
- But surely it is not only the humanists who ought to worry about the failure of community, or about the
dangerous erosion in the postmodern world of any space for meaningful resistance. Tabbi does not claim
that we
ought to accept such an erosion blithely. Still, the particular variety of cognitive science he
chooses to articulate
together with systems theory leads him to recreate on the critical-theoretical level some of the same problems he
insightfully exposes in the fictions he studies.
Fine Arts and Humanities Division
Elizabethtown Community and Technical College
stephen.dougherty@kctcs.edu
COPYRIGHT (c) 2004 BY Steven Dougherty.
READERS MAY USE PORTIONS
OF THIS WORK IN ACCORDANCE WITH THE FAIR USE PROVISIONS OF U.S. COPYRIGHT
LAW. IN ADDITION, SUBSCRIBERS AND MEMBERS OF SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTIONS MAY
USE THE ENTIRE WORK FOR ANY INTERNAL NONCOMMERCIAL PURPOSE BUT, OTHER THAN
ONE COPY SENT BY EMAIL, PRINT OR FAX TO ONE PERSON AT ANOTHER LOCATION FOR
THAT INDIVIDUAL'S PERSONAL USE, DISTRIBUTION OF THIS ARTICLE OUTSIDE OF A
SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION FROM EITHER THE
AUTHOR OR THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS IS EXPRESSLY FORBIDDEN.
THIS ARTICLE AND OTHER CONTENTS OF THIS ISSUE ARE
AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE UNTIL RELEASE OF THE NEXT ISSUE. A
TEXT-ONLY ARCHIVE OF THE JOURNAL IS ALSO AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE. FOR
FULL HYPERTEXT ACCESS TO BACK ISSUES, SEARCH UTILITIES, AND OTHER VALUABLE
FEATURES, YOU OR YOUR INSTITUTION MAY SUBSCRIBE TO
PROJECT MUSE, THE
ON-LINE JOURNALS PROJECT OF THE JOHNS
HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS.
Works Cited
Fodor, Jerry. The Mind Doesn't Work That Way: The Scope and Limits of
Computational Psychology. Cambridge: MIT P, 2000.
|