What Remains to be Seen? The Rhetoric of Witnessing
Morris's Fog documents further written recollections published by McNamara over the last fifteen years that
try to account for the unprecedented violence
that has occurred since the First World War. Titles such as Wilson's Ghost: Reducing the Risk of Killing and
Catastrophe; In Retrospect: The Tragedy and Lessons Of Vietnam; and Argument Without End: In
Search of Answers to the Vietnam Tragedy certainly indicate a keen historical focus, but also McNamara's
personal commitment to persuading others about the perils of the future threatened by the
remains of the past. Initially, McNamara's writing provides a
corrective for the political misjudgments influenced by the predominance
of a Cold War perspective. This motivation for critique, however, is
haunted by a more looming threat than just cautionary advice about the
limits of perspective. The Cold War grounded in nuclear build-up
is the advent of conflict haunted by a decisive possibility that would
end politics, the polis, and perhaps the world. The optimism evident
in post-World War hope for a "war that would end all wars" has ironically
been resignified. McNamara's writing is haunted by the possibility
of a "war that would end all wars," because he witnessed
this possibility. If war indeed fogs and confuses judgment, his
purpose is to show that the competitive logic of war always points
toward an imperative guided by a nuclear logic.
A rhetoric of responsibility that thematizes McNamara's written work
also orients the lessons in Morris's film. Responsibility as an evaluative
duty is evident near the film's end, when McNamara turns to the poetry
of T.S. Eliot to grasp the force of his need to recollect, to witness
his past.
"We shall not cease from exploring And at the end of our exploration
We will return to where we started
And know this place for the first time"[1]
McNamara's citation from the Four Quartets--which does not conceive
of and so defends against the prospect of a radical end, such as nuclear
annihilation--indicates the conventional sense of responsibility
as the duty to explore ceaselessly, but the responsibility of exploration
has a reactive energy of recollection that is divided. McNamara's
recollections have a retrogressive, circular movement projected backward
that returns in memory, gathering the remains to return to a momentary
place anew. In "knowing this place for the first time," he must
return, recollect, and clear the fog that has confused him and so many
others of his generation. Yet the desire to step out of the fog and
gain the proximity that would provide clarity to some beginning is threatened
by the same opacity that he wants to lighten. To begin again at a
place with full knowing may be nothing more than naïve nostalgia
for a purified point of origin.
And yet, in nearly every way, Morris's McNamara is a confident evaluator,
assured of his interpretive decision to "return to where we started"
historically. The documentary begins with a montage of post-World
War/Cold War images that ends with a shot of McNamara during his service
as Secretary of Defense preparing for a television press conference
and questioning the television crews, "are you ready? All set?"
Morris draws attention to the equivocal nature of origin as well as
to the equivocal authority McNamara has over the archive with an opening
interchange that seems to build a clever transition from the press conference
decades ago to the present filming. At the beginning of Fog,
McNamara prepares himself for the interview by asking the
filmmaker to speak in a practiced tone so he could
clearly hear the questions. After practicing voice levels, McNamara
states authoritatively and efficiently that he does not need to "go
back":
"Now I remember exactly the sentence I left off on. I remember
how it started, and I was cut off in the middle. But you can fix
it up someway. I don't want to go back, introduce the sentence,
because I know exactly what I wanted to say."
Just as we know that this film is constructed by editing, we see
and hear McNamara directing some of the editing. The decision
to begin the film with a seemingly incidental matter is more than just
clever. McNamara's comments introduced us
to a very precise and efficient man who knows exactly what he "want[s]
to say." Such certainty is not just momentary;
McNamara has to some extent a very clear evaluation of the fog that
has clouded the twentieth century. His desire to convey a precise
viewpoint is clear in Morris's documentary, and
is also evident in his written work, which is as clear, efficient,
and logical as fine technical writing.
This desire for efficiency is exemplified in recollections that produce what Kenneth Burke calls an "analysis of
analysis"
(Burke 9). On topics ranging from the Cuban Missile Crisis to
the Vietnam war, McNamara is insistent that the fog of the Cold War
concealed, for good or for ill, underlying cultural, political, and
moral principles that could have resulted in political negotiation
that may have minimized the needless killing and massive destruction
suffered over the second half of the twentieth century. In many
ways his judgment that historical myopia guided U.S. foreign policy
seems generally correct, and his support of this evaluation is compelling. The lessons Morris culls from McNamara's
testimony are most forceful when the filmmaker highlights the United
States' sense of its worldwide destiny and,
thus, of global responsibility, a state that was often motivated by political imperialism.
McNamara's keen analysis of an ideological paradigm that underwrote all decisions for many decades is understood more
subtly as a
"terminal incapacity" (7). Kenneth Burke argues that terminal
incapacity occurs when one's very abilities function as blindness (7). The
resolution to fight the threat of the Triple Axis in World War II reinforces
the resolve to battle a new enemy--worldwide communism. Thereafter,
the U.S. response to the threat of the spread of communism becomes
programmatic, and the U.S. cannot envision subtle social, cultural, and political
problems that might open a different perspective on its dreaded responsibility. The U.S. ability to fight communism
produced
a resolve to do so that finally blinded or incapacitated the U.S.'s
ability to evaluate its anti-communist goals and the means with which
it secured them. In the end, McNamara provides the viewer with
a cautionary critique, lessons that clarify the past and help envision the
future.
And yet, he still mourns.
We don't want to dismiss entirely the use of personal evaluation,
the wisdom of an elder statesman recollecting his political life as
a testimony for the future. The future is customarily presumed
to be a reconstitution of the past. Yet, there remains a
sense of responsibility that binds McNamara. In one sense, he
cites an evaluative efficiency that binds his responsibility, and yet
he remains bound by another responsibility that provokes him beyond
reason. McNamara's ongoing lessons about responsibility are haunted
by a summons to which he often responds with trembling. What he has
seen is threatened further by what he has not seen--indeed, by what he
has seen he has not seen, what he would give us to see. McNamara
never saw the faces of the hundred thousand Japanese civilians killed
by a firestorm during the World War II bombings in Japan. What he did
see--the singular spectacle of Quaker Norman Morrison, his body ablaze
in protest--brings him to interiorize in mourning the faceless thousands
incinerated in Japan, Vietnam, and many _____ elsewhere yet to come.
Franklin is the spectacle that actualizes "the truth of the mourning
of the other...who always speaks in me before me" (Derrida, Mémoires 29).
McNamara's recollections in the film
are another attempt to bring clarity to a call that haunts him, to evoke
the unseen faces that might authorize the summons. Further, his
persistence in re-facing his former enemies--Castro's face, the faces of Vietnamese
leaders, and the faces of others--shows McNamara's need
to personify and endow with a sense of presence, clarity, and authority a summons
that resists location. In the end, we believe that McNamara's
exhortations summon these specters for the viewer, so that we might
also see and feel--in the absence of the face of the other, of the other
others whose ashes cover the face of the world--the grave responsibility
that remains.
Faced with McNamara's lessons of hope for empathy and renewed rationality,
the viewer is also challenged by a kind of physical pressure. We are not offering detail in
place of argument when we point
out that the viewer cannot overlook Robert McNamara's presence in the
film: his face, his voice, and his eyes. His direct, pervasive
presence is not solely a matter of Morris's Interrotron.[2] In Fog, McNamara seems almost to enter our space.
His urgent tone and direct gestures seem to project forward, penetrating
the film's virtual space to assure us of his counsel. This guidance
is expressed in a proud voice that wavers somewhere
between warning and remorse. Quite starkly, Morris's most pressing
close-ups encounter McNamara's eyes fogged with a watery kind of melancholy
filled by the confusion of responsibility. We cannot look past
his eyes tinged with remorse, betrayed by his most powerful personal
talent: the force of analytical reason. Foremost, we cannot look
past his eyes because his mourning of reason strains to perceive another form that can account for experiences that exceed his understanding. He, or Morris, wants us to see him seeing (at)
those limits.
In mourning, we turn to the profound writing of Jacques Derrida because
no other thinker has shown us with so much insight and patience the
importance of mourning what is to come: the crisis of the future. Derrida remains the great thinker of the
future, a future that
is an absolute threat.
Ceaseless Mourning: What Remains to Be Thought
War, ultimately from the Indo-European wers-,
to confuse, mix up.
--Adapted from The American Heritage Dictionary of Indo-European
Roots (77)
Haunted by the spectralizing effects of the remains, McNamara's answers to the questions Morris poses offer themselves to
be read in a certain way[3]--that
is, as scenes, acts, and gestures in an incomplete, indeed an incompletable,
work of mourning.
No doubt McNamara entertains no such intent. From the beginning to
the end of the interview, McNamara directs his discussions and arguments
toward the absolute urgency of certain "lessons." These are not the
eleven often deeply ironic lessons Morris uses to punctuate his film,
but ten nation-guiding principles McNamara has formulated in the explicit
hope of refocusing present and future American military and foreign
policy. Although Morris does not include them in his film (he appends
them in a "special feature" to The Fog of War's DVD release),
they inform all McNamara's discussions. Indeed, the
imperative to which McNamara's principles attempt to answer constitutes
the horizon of his sense of the nation's collective responsibility to
itself and to the world. Over and over, then, McNamara's responses to
Morris underscore the central--the nuclear--imperative to which he testifies:
America in particular, the world more generally, must reduce the threat
of nuclear war and the frequency and virulence of conventional war in
the twenty-first century.
This imperative--with its psychological urgency on
the one hand, its force of moral necessity on the other--imposes a ceaseless work of mourning that provokes the subject
to yet further mourning rather than aiding the subject to bring grief
to an end. The reason is that a certain irremediable loss, a loss itself
lost to understanding, permeates McNamara's pedagogical aims and opens
his discourse to what might be called the lesson of his lessons. This
lesson of the lessons, a lesson, therefore, without lesson,
is that there is something utterly unlearnable about war from war, something
unlearnable about human fallibility. This unlearnability poses deep
problems for individual and collective
responsibility in the realm of political decisions, and it is a something
that cannot be broached except by way of a mourning that does not end.
1.1 The Lesson of the Lessons, the Lessons without Lesson
"My rule is, try to learn, try to understand . . . develop the lessons
and try to pass them on."
--McNamara, The Fog of War.
"One has to think and never be sure of thinking."
--Blanchot, The Writing of the Disaster (145).
Morris organizes The Fog of War around a series of eleven
aphoristic "lessons" which he draws from McNamara's own words, often
quoting him directly. A close inspection of these lessons indicates
the dramatic irony of their central contradiction: a heightened consciousness
is necessary and yet insufficient for learning what must be learned
from war--from thinking about war and from thinking about thinking about
war.[4] A similar inspection of McNamara's
own lessons--which are much less gnomically conceived principles than
Morris's, and which arise out of McNamara's experiences in the Pentagon,
out of his deep apprehensions about nuclear armaments, and out of his
judgment that it is absolutely necessary to reduce "the brutality of
war," "the level of killing," and the threat of terrorism--shows that they, too, are
essentially contradictory. One of their greatest
ironies derives from the way they specify incompatible goals--above all
the contradictory goal of maintaining the sovereignty of the United
States on the one hand and an imaginary sovereignty of a universal political
entity to come--"the human race" or "society as a whole"--on the other.[5]
If both sets of lessons are similar in being contradictory, even if
they are contradictory in dissimilar ways, they are also both offered
as "lessons," a term Morris and McNamara alike employ uncritically.
Morris and McNamara each thematizes his pedagogical aims but not the
value of the presumptive value of those aims--in other words, not the
possible lessons that might be drawn from attempting to draw lessons
from war. What, then, does the word lesson disclose about the
meaning and force of McNamara's and Morris's lessons? More importantly,
what does the word lesson disclose about the points of view and
assumptions this term conceals?
According to The American Heritage Dictionary of Indo-European
Roots, the word lesson derives from a stem, leg-,
to collect "with derivates meaning to speak'" (35). According to Shipley, it means to "gather, set in order; consider, choose; then read,
speak" (209). This root has given rise to the Greek stems legein,
to gather, speak, and logos, speech, word, reason. The two are
the source of, among their English derivatives, lexicon, dialect,
logic, and logistics as well as of apology. In its
descent through the Latin, legere, to gather, choose, pluck,
read, leg- has generated such terms as legend, legible,
legion, collect, and intelligent, as well as sortilege,
neglect, and sacrilege. Possibly through the Latin lex,
law, it has eventuated in legal, legitimate, loyal,
legislator, and privilege; and possibly through legare,
to dispute, commission, charge, it has produced allege and legacy.
More directly than many words, "lesson" inherits an overdetermined
range of connotation and denotation. Bearing above all the metaphysical
legacy of the logos, the word "lesson" capitalizes on those
intellectual traditions in which knowledge is conceived as a potentially
transcendental force, a life-protecting force, which provides humans
a means of surviving their violence. The word "lesson," then, functions
symptomatically as a wish-fulfillment and thus as an expression of the
anxiety the wish-fulfillment would relieve. Would that there were or
could be lessons from war. If such lessons are possible, then such knowledge
might enable humans to reduce their dependence on war. If such lessons
are not possible, then advances in techno-scientific knowledge--and the
annihilative military and terrorist purposes to which such knowledge
is predicted to be put--are likely to be apocalyptic.
McNamara is explicit about his fear. It is the theme of all of his
remarks. In the section of the documentary that proceeds under the title
"Rationality Will Not Save Us," McNamara attributes the avoidance, to
date, of nuclear holocaust to sheer "luck!" He warns: "That danger exists
today, the danger of total destruction of one's society." He attempts
to formalize this warning in his second and deeply paradoxical lesson
concerning the unpredictable consequences of the "human fallibility":
"The indefinite combination of human fallibility and nuclear weapons
will lead to the destruction of nations." Morris reduces this observation
to a caution about the limits of rationality. Thus, whereas Morris stipulates
the limits of a rationality that, by itself, "will not save us," and holds open the possibility that
something other than
or in addition to rationality might, McNamara declares that a destruction
beyond all remediation "will" happen for reasons of a "fallibility"
that is inherent in if not constitutive of humanness in general, not
just of particular (rational) modes or forms of human thought. In his
tenth lesson, then, McNamara invokes not only the specter of the nuclear
terrorism that threatens "nations"--nations in general, all nations, the identifying names of which become irrelevant in relation to the
nuclear annihilation that would destroy the archive of names along with
nations--but also the fact of American responsibility for contributing
to this peril: "One of the greatest dangers we face today is the risk
that terrorists will obtain access to weapons of mass destruction as
a result of the breakdown of the Non-Proliferation Regime. We in the
U.S. are contributing to that breakdown." In these two lessons, then,
McNamara specifies the apotropaic meaning of his use of the word "lesson,"
which marks the apocalyptic tone of his entire discourse, of his entire
testimony.
McNamara twice identifies the uncanny source of his fear, and thus
of what will have been his future testimony before Morris's camera. The
first revelation occurs in his dispassionate observation that "there will
be no learning period with nuclear weapons." The second occurs
when he reports on his visit to Cuba in 1992 and his highly emotional
confrontation with Castro over the missile crisis thirty years earlier.
He recalls that he learned for the first time that "162 nuclear warheads,
including 90 tactical warheads, were on the island at the time of this
critical moment of the crisis." He is flabbergasted: "I couldn't believe
what I was hearing, and Castro got very angry with me because I said,
'Mr. President, let's stop this meeting. This is totally new to me.
I'm not sure I got the translation right.'" But the meeting proceeded,
and McNamara recalls having asked Castro three questions the answers
to which instantly excite in him a simultaneous disbelief in and yet
utterly appalled acceptance of what he is hearing:
Mr. President, I have three questions to you. Number one: did you know the nuclear weapons were there?
Number two: if you did, would you have recommended to Khrushchev in the face of a U.S. attack that he use
them? Number three: if he had used them, what would have happened to Cuba?
Castro answers yes to the first question. To the second, Castro answers
no, not would have but did: "I would not have recommended
to Khrushchev, I did recommend to Khrushchev that they be used." And
to McNamara's third question, Castro evidently replies that Cuba "would
have been totally destroyed" and then adds: "Mr. McNamara, if you and
President Kennedy had been in a similar situation, that's what you would
have done." Although McNamara repudiates Castro's assertion, his emotion in remembering the exchange
as well as during the encounter itself suggest that he now knows Castro could be right.
In the moment he hears Castro's third answer, McNamara is beside himself--literally
so, for he is borne away by a dread that makes him tremble in the knowledge
not only that he is learning something he had not known during the missile crisis, but something he had not known he had not known
about the mindset of his opponent and of himself. He now knows that
his double ignorance could have led to a nuclear confrontation.
In other words, in the moment of gaining access to his abyssal self-ignorance,
McNamara is forced to see his past blindness. At that moment he envisions
the unimaginable--an apocalyptic future that was avoided not by insight
or foresight but by blind luck. More generally, he is on the verge of
glimpsing the possibility of a present and future blindness that
could not be revealed as such until afterward. If he knows that
"it's almost impossible for our people today to put themselves back
into that period," then he must suspect the terrible consequence: it
will be "almost impossible" for "our people today" to learn from "that
period." Therefore, when, near the beginning of the film, McNamara says
that "at 85, I can look back," he is not necessarily claiming a specular
privilege but confessing, rather, the spectacular structural sightlessness
that attaches to every experience of oneself in the present. "We all make mistakes," McNamara says
near the end of the film. What
prevents this assertion from being a pious cliché is
that McNamara not only knows that "our understanding, our judgment,
is inadequate," but suspects that such knowledge about the fragility
and incompleteness of knowledge comes only in hindsight, only belatedly,
which is to say always too late.
However, whether or not he grasps it, the lesson of his lessons is
that he could not deduce, invent, or otherwise recognize the specific
lessons during the experiences which only in retrospect produce them.
The lesson of the lessons is not in their content. The essential feature
of each of the lessons is not the lesson itself. Rather, the lesson
of the lessons is that they are without lesson: they do not summarize
a formalizable knowledge that can be taught, learned, transmitted. The
lessons are untimely, and the lesson of these lessons is that they can
never present themselves as such precisely when they are most needed.
Or, rather, the lesson of McNamara's lessons is that he has intuited
something about the nature of knowing, especially in times of crisis
when unprecedented events unfold in unprecedented ways such that
one must reckon with what exceeds present categories of comprehension,
decision, action, and anticipatable consequence, putting one in the position
of having to invent on the spot new means of responding to the danger
at hand.
McNamara's earlier understanding of this intractable double bind demonstrates how difficult
it is to escape the effects
of this bind at the very moment of recognizing it. A third of the way
through the film, a younger McNamara, then Secretary of Defense, admits:
"There's much I don't know I don't know." Affirming the logical necessity
of this proposition, he laughs awkwardly, unable to confront its emotional
force, its affective power, which will overtake him years later as one
signal of what yet remains to haunt him. Years before he will have been
haunted, the Secretary of Defense does not grasp the import of his insight
as an index of the inescapable possibility that every present self-declaration
can be caught up in a dramatic irony to which the speaker
is blind. Not simply blindness, then, and not even blindness to one's
blindness, but the possibility of being blind and the unavailability
of a means for determining whether or not one really is--it is this condition
of possibly inevitable self-ignorance that constitutes the nuclear
core of the terrible fallibility to which McNamara bears witness. In
testifying to the need to learn something from the history of war in
the twentieth-century and from the prospective nuclear eventuality he
fears is inevitable, he testifies to the failure of his testimony and
acts out the second-order cognitive fallibility that is an inescapable feature of this very testimony.
In other words, McNamara's lessons are literally irresponsible--that
is, non-responsive to the realities they would negotiate--for a reason
that is structural to human consciousness and is not merely the consequence
of a faulty or self-protecting memory. McNamara does not quite deduce
this consequence. At the end of the film, however, he acts it out in
a performative declaration that gives the lie not to the specific substance
of his lessons but to their meta-level efficacy, to their ability to
be sent and received as lessons. In the film's epilogue, he balks at
talking further about his responsibilities concerning the Vietnam War:
"You don't know what I know," he says. He is talking specifically
"about how inflammatory my words can be." And yet his statement has
an immeasurably greater pertinence, for the problem of the
kinds of lessons to which McNamara would testify is that any
such lesson requires knowing what one does not know one does not know,
and a willingness to open oneself to the prospect of having to engage
in an impossible act of self-recognition, a self-remarking that gives
and withdraws the very possibility of witnessing.
1.2 The Necessity and Impossibility of Witnessing
"As we know, there are known knowns. There are things we know
we know.
We also know there are known unknowns. That is to say we know there are some things we do
not know. But there are also unknown unknowns, the ones we don't know we don't know."
--Donald Rumsfeld, DOD news briefing, 12 February 2002.
1.21 Epistemological Asymmetry
There is a fundamental difference between the consciousness of self
and the consciousness of other. It appears that each person has a direct,
immediate, and privileged access to part of his or her own mind that is denied
to others, who for their part have only an indirect and mediated access
to anyone else's "first-person" mental state. A person seems to be
able to know his or her own mind by an act of self-reflection. "The
certitude of inner existence, Husserl thinks, has no need to be signified.
It is immediately present to itself. It is living consciousness"
(Derrida, Speech and Phenomena 43). But no such act of self-reflection
will enable an individual to know the mind of the other in the same
way. The result is an epistemological asymmetry between what
an I can know of itself and what the same I can know
of another. This asymmetry is built into the very structure of consciousness,
and it blocks each and every I from knowing others or being
known by them in the way that this I knows--or thinks it knows--itself.
People tend to experience the asymmetry narcissistically--that is, as
the richness of their own consciousness of themselves as opposed to
the much poorer knowledge others seem to have of them. Who would trade
the consciousness they have of themselves for the consciousness others have of them?
However, the certainty attaching to the experience of one's own self-consciousness,
a certainty in which Descartes sought a foundation
for knowledge, may always be less accurate, less reliable, less
truthful than the knowledge others have of oneself. One reason for this derives from the
tautological nature of knowing or believing something to be
the case. If a person holds a belief, he or she cannot simultaneously
believe that this belief is in error. If an I knows or thinks
it knows something to be the case, this I cannot simultaneously
know in the present moment that it is mistaken, if it
is. The grammatical (present) tense of this tautology is not accidental:
anyone can, in principle, come to recognize that a belief they had
previously affirmed is false, that they can have held a mistaken
belief. However, at the moment, the person cannot simultaneously
believe that the belief is true. A person can believe (or think he or
she believes) or not; but this person cannot both believe and not believe
what he or she believes.
And yet others might very well recognize that I am in error,
if I am, in believing what I (think I) believe.
What is more, others might also be in a position to recognize not only
that, because I believe what I believe, I
do not and cannot presently experience the falsity of my belief (under
the circumstances, once again, that I am, in fact, harboring
a false belief). This means that others are able, in principle, to occupy
an epistemological position that remains out of reach for me: others
can know that I am wrong; they can know that I do
not know that I am wrong; they can know that I do
not know that they (or someone else) might know what I do not;
and they can know that I am not merely wrong, and not merely
unaware of my ignorance, but unaware of my unawareness of my ignorance,
and so on, at the very moment that I am convinced that I
know what I (think I) know.
Under these circumstances, it would behoove me to bracket my (false)
consciousness of myself, my mistaken belief, and to become as open as
possible to the other's consciousness of my error--indeed, for the other's
awareness of my unawareness of my unawareness.
And yet such an attitude remains difficult to achieve, especially when
my emotional state reinforces my sense of knowing what I know.
The experience of being impassioned--angry, for example--very often heightens
the (potentially illusory) sense of certitude attaching to my experience
of my own beliefs, my own knowledge, especially when the object of that
knowledge is someone with whom I am angry. To be sure, it is
possible to recognize the possibility that my emotional state
is affecting my perceptions; it is even possible to count to ten before
responding. Both possibilities,
however, affirm the commonplace experience that the feeling of anger
often intensifies the certitude with which one (thinks one) knows something
to be the case.
The experience of knowing or seeming to know what one knows inscribes
human consciousness within an untranscendable horizon; at the same time,
however, it programs human consciousness--at least that form of consciousness
that has developed from the tradition of western metaphysics--to
experience its inscription not as a confinement within an unsurpassable
limit but as a freedom that offers precisely the promise of transcendence
in the form of access to truth itself.
Derrida generalizes this irony in Of Grammatology when he
summarizes the phenomenological experience of "hearing oneself think."
Consciousness, especially in its form as conscience, he notes, seems
to occur as an unmediated self-voicing in which one's thought is available
to oneself as a signified that is seemingly independent of any signifier,
and that therefore has a completely non-material being, a non-material
presence to the subject that hears itself thinking. "This experience
of the effacement of the signifier in the voice is not merely one illusion
among many--since it is the condition of the very idea of truth. . . . This illusion is the
history of truth" (20). The history of
truth is the history of the attempt to recuperate the knowledge of self
as superior to the other's (potential) knowledge of the self's (potentially
abyssal) self-ignorance. For this reason the truth of the truth--the
truth that the experience of truth derives from an illusory experience
of seeming self-presence--cannot be introjected, cannot become the non-illusory basis of the
experience of one's self-consciousness.
The reason is evident in the paradox, notoriously remarked by
Donald Rumsfeld, that one can know that there are "unknown
unknowns" but, by definition, not know what they are. Here, Rumsfeld
can represent the world, including his enemies. He can represent his
representations of himself. What is more, he can represent his self-representations
as limited, partial, possibly erroneous or self-deluding. He can even
represent the possibility that he might not know something, not know
that he does not know it, and thus not be able to represent the limit
that cuts, divides, or separates him from the very knowledge he thinks
he has. What Rumsfeld intuits, in short, is that insofar as the object
of knowing is subject to an indeterminate future falsifiability, self-consciousness
is a source of radical epistemological provisionality. Indeed, it is
a source of epistemological self-impoverishment. The catastrophe of
self-consciousness is not its capacity for an
infinitely regressive series of self-inclusive self-representations
but its irreparable incapacity for representing the error of
its representations (if and when they can be determined to be in error), except belatedly.
What turns the screw of catastrophe ever tighter is the further paradox that each of us can have, in principle, more accurate beliefs
about the beliefs of others than those around us, who can also
have more accurate beliefs about our beliefs than we can. These two
asymmetries do not balance or cancel each other out but double and redouble
each other ad infinitum. They mark and remark a rationally determinable
structural boundary to rationality, a limit condition that can be specified
from one side, as it were, but not from the other--the one side emerging
only when the I foregoes its presumptive privilege of attesting
to itself, to its knowledge of itself.
1.22 Declining to Witness
At the same time, in specifying its knowledge of the other, the I can never entirely separate itself from a minimal assertion
about what it (thinks it) knows of itself. The I that knows
that the other does not know its error is an I that is always
in the position of knowing (or thinking that it knows) that it knows.
In other words, the predication "I know" means "(I think) I know that
I know," and for this reason the I cannot assume the position
of the other; that is, the I cannot become the other
who knows what it (some I) does not know it does not know of
itself. Only another other, an other that does not say "I," an other that cannot say
"I," an other that is therefore not
simply another human subject able to speak in the first person--only
this other other could know what any human subject, appearing to speak
to or for or from itself, cannot know and cannot know it cannot know.
If bearing witness presupposes a first-person predication, then this
other other can never bear witness to my false beliefs. Its meta-level
knowledge would not be recuperable as a form of self-consciousness.
This other other is not a you that says "I." In not being able
to say "I"--and thus in not being able to say "I see," "I know that you
do not know," "I recognize that you do not recognize that you do not
know," and so on--this other other could witness what no I can witness
of itself or any other I, what, in fact, no one who ever says
"I" can witness.
Consciousness is a disaster, then, precisely insofar as it precipitates
each I into a position of thinking it knows, precisely insofar
as it cuts each I off from the possibility of speaking without
saying "I," without embedding its knowledge and its representations
of its knowledge in a self-referential, hence self-interested, frame.
This is a secret that consciousness keeps from itself within itself, even
when it reveals this secret to itself: I can never know, until some
future moment, whether or not my present beliefs are in the name of
a value other than self-interest--for example, the value of a truth that
would not participate in the illusory experience of self-certainty.
I can never make that future moment come to pass. I can never make it
arrive. I can never say: "Now, at last, I know. Now I finally know that
I know."[6]
1.23 Deciding--For and Against
On this count, how should McNamara be judged? As Alexander Cockburn
shows, throughout the interviews McNamara misremembers
and occludes the historical record, construes his behavior in self-serving
ways, and otherwise inauthenticates himself. If one were to bracket
McNamara's personal fallibility, however, there would remain the problem
of an impersonal fallibility within the very structure of knowing and
acting. This fallibility takes the form of unforeseen
or unintended consequences, of unwanted outcomes, of results that those
who initiate a course of events might be the first to repudiate on moral
or ethical grounds--in other words, of developments for which no one r
can take responsibility. "Do you feel in any way responsible for the
[Vietnam] war? Do you feel guilty?" Morris asks. McNamara answers: "I
don't want to say any more."[7]
One might wish to condemn McNamara for his evasions--indeed, for his evasion of his evasions--especially
on the matter of America's invasion
in Southeast Asia. And yet it is also possible that McNamara cuts off
the exchange precisely because responsibility can never be a matter
of a sorrowful, rueful, or otherwise mournful subject coming to accept
a determinable responsibility that originates in this person's decisions
and actions. It is possible, then, that McNamara does not want to answer
Morris because he has caught a glimpse of a responsibilit--yan impossible,
unforgivable responsibility--to which he does not know how to respond, and for which he does not
know whether or not it would be possible to know
what his responsibilities would be.
Responsibility requires decision, and decision entails not just lost
opportunities but infinite opportunity costs. Every decision cuts off
all other possible futures in order to deliver what will have been a
particular future. To decide,
then, is to impose a –cidal fate upon what might have been.
It is to beckon toward what cannot come to pass, hence cannot die either. It is to cut off and so lose what, in not coming into
being, cannot be lost as such, and thus would be a loss before and beyond
loss, a death before and beyond death, a loss or a death without loss
or death.
McNamara might be understood as struggling to articulate a version
of this insight. "Historians don't really like to deal with counter-factuals,
with what might have been," he declares in the film. When he then adds
that, "Well, I know a few things," he is not asserting a positive or
empirical knowledge based on experience but anticipating what he shortly
thereafter calls the "fog of war." This metaphorical fog itself does
not cloud judgment but rather foregrounds what does--namely, the beclouded
and beclouding nature of all judgment with respect to the futures that
are decided against, consciously or not, in coming to any decision.
That is why he ruminates on his guilt not so much for a decision he
made as for a corporate decision which blocks any simple attribution
or acceptance of blame: "in order to win a war, should you kill 100,000
people in one night by firebombing or any other way?" he asks, having
recalled his part in the military "mechanism that in a sense recommended"
just such a decision--namely, "killing 50% to 90% of the people of 67
Japanese cities and then bombing them with two nuclear bombs."
When McNamara invokes the "mechanism" of decision-making, he admits
that the decision in question must--absolutely must--be faulted, but he em
also recognizes it is an empty gesture to take the burden of fault on himself
no matter how much others might want him to or even how much he might
want to: "LeMay said, If we'd lost the war, we'd all have been prosecuted
as war criminals.' And I think he's right. He, and I'd say I, were behaving
as war criminals." McNamara knows that the "fog" of war--the "fog" that
renders responsibility impossibly irresponsible--is not limited to war
but is a feature of all decision: "Our understanding, our judgment,
is inadequate." If his pronouncement is bathetic, it nevertheless speaks
to the terrible knowledge of what cuts him off from the we (the
100,000 dead among so many others) at the very moment he invokes a community of like
minds, of the we whose understanding and judgment
are in adequate.
Vis-à-vis the lost futures entailed in any decision, the inadequacy
is radical. It is no wonder that McNamara would seek, in the words he
loves from Eliot, to "know the place for the first time"--as if it were s
possible to abide in a moment of time before the onset not only of loss
but of all the losses that have been and will continue to be lost. These
lost losses proceed from out of the very act of deciding, from out of
the instant of decision,[8] for one never decides in the name
of life alone without deciding also in the name of a nameless and incalculable
deathliness. Having to decide means having to decide against life in
deciding for life. War invariably makes such implication explicit.
The memory of those decisions produces a ceaseless work of mourning.
1.3 Memory and Mourning
"Let me just ask the TV--are you ready?"
--Robert McNamara, The Fog of War
The therapeutic disciplines typically distinguish between normal and pathological
grief in mourning. Freud, for example, contrasts melancholia with a more typical
course of grieving. In melancholia, Freud says, the individual "knows
whom he has lost but not what it is he has lost in them" ("Mourning
and Melancholia" 166). In normal mourning, even at its most severe,
however, the individual does not suffer this unknowing: "there is nothing
unconscious about the loss," and thus nothing unknowable about the source
of the individual's suffering or its psychodynamic course. The result
is that "the testing of reality, having shown that the loved object
no longer exists, requires forthwith that all the libido shall be withdrawn
from its attachments to this object" 165-66). This withdrawal is often t
exceedingly difficult. The individual must convert the representation
of the loved object as living into a representation of the loved object
as dead or permanently gone, as thereafter irrecoverable, as irreparably
mute before the desire of the one who remains. "Each single one of the
memories and hopes" by which the survivor had been libidinally invested
in or "bound . . . to the object" must be "brought up and hyper-cathected"
so as to "detach" this person's libido and enable it to be redirected
toward the world of the living. The grieving individual, Freud suggests,
knows this quite well. And yet Freud finds himself unable to explain
either "why this process of carrying out the behest of reality bit by
bit . . . should be so extraordinarily painful" or why the pain should
"seem natural to us" (166). Normal grief proceeds from something unknowable, a pain that,
because it "seems natural," conceals its essential mystery, its essential
unknowability, its essential non-essentiality.
As has been suggested, this double, indeed abyssal unknowability
permeates the very structure of consciousness, which is incapable
of representing and introjecting the lost losses that are a consequence
of every decision. For this reason, then, consciousness is implicated
in a work of mourning that can never, in principle, bring the process
of withdrawing its "cathexes" from the lost object to an end. The reason
is simple: the very basis of any decision is a simultaneous psychic
investment and disinvestment. Cathexis to a loved object
is always a refusal to cathect to all the other possible objects. It
is a non-cathexis in them, a blocking off or even blotting out of them.
Cathexis itself entails a form of the very withdrawal of cathexis that
Freud considers to be the mystery of grief and its pain. Cathexis
to is simultaneously decathexis from: cathectic attachment
to a loved object is from its onset a version of the decathexis
from by which the subject is formed or constituted in a
mourning without end, in the ceaseless work of mourning that attends
all identifications and object choices and thereafter all decision.
In Mémoires, "Dialanguages," and elsewhere, Derrida
has explained that one can never completely assimilate the dead other,
who remains before and after the interiorizing movement of mourning.
All the more so would the other others remain beyond cathectic or decathectic
appropriation. For this reason, then, all object choice, all cathexis
and its decathectic self-preservation upon the death of the object,
inscribes psychic life within a structure of cutting, of -cision, the
fatality of which McNamara attempts to witness.
The shared etymology of memory and mourning points to
the identity of attachment and loss, love and grief. Both memory
and mourning descend from a common Indo-European stem, (s)mer-,
to remember. This root has given rise to the Germanic murnan,
to remember sorrowfully, the origin of mourn, and to the Latin
memor, mindful, the source of memory, remember,
commemorate, and other cognate terms (American Heritage Dictionary
62). These etymologies suggest that memory--the "very essence of the
psyche" in Freud's model, as Derrida explains in "Freud and the
Scene of Writing" 199--is inseparable from the work of mourning. If
the heart of mourning is an experience of loss, then so too would be the condition of the possibility of a subject's
self-relation, of its
auto-affection. Psychic life would begin with a movement of ontological
subtraction. However, if the heart of mourning is not a loss that can
be experienced but an incalculable loss of what will never have been--of losses that were
never present to be subsequently lost, of losses that
can never be recalled, of losses that are lost as losses--then the condition
of the possibility of psychic life would be absolutely mournful.
Anticipating his listeners' unbelief, the first-person subject of
Errol Morris's documentary--the person who is still moved to tears by
his memory of John F. Kennedy and this President's determination to
prevent nuclear war--this person, Robert Strange McNamara, insists that
he can remember the celebration in San Francisco at the end of World
War I. His first memory, then, would be from as early as the age of two,
and it is this: "My earliest memory is of a city exploding with
joy"
Exploding in Sorrow: The Remains of the Dead
The future can only be anticipated in the form of an absolute
danger.
--Jacques Derrida Of Grammatology
'If we'd lost the war, we'd all have been prosecuted as war criminals.'
And I think he's right. He, and I'd say I, were behaving as war criminals.
LeMay recognized that what he was doing would be thought immoral if
his side had lost. But what makes it immoral if you lose and not immoral
if you win?"
--Robert
McNamara, The Fog of War
McNamara tries to access some reason
that will stop the world from ceaseless mourning, but in sorrow he is
haunted by the vague sense that such reason itself might be the threat
he fears.
Any ethical principle remains threatened by the velocity and efficiency of competition that is the essence of
warfare. The lessons of war seem to arrive too late. In McNamara's
economy of decision, war demands that "one must do evil in order
to produce good." However, as Derrida reminds us, the advent of
the nuclear age may introduce a new rate of speed and temporality so
effective that it erases all competence in a feverish drive to dominate
("No Apocalypse, Not Now" 20). It is this unprecedented
rate of speed and competition that McNamara tentatively begins to intuit
as a kind of evil because implosion is its telos. As an efficiency expert,
McNamara is guided by reason. He
understands very clearly that nuclear weapons are efficient while his work is a plea for political and military
initiatives that are essentially slow and inefficient: reasoned judgment, deliberation, negotiation,
and internationalism. Few within international politics would argue
with such sound judgment. And yet this sound, reasonable advice does
not seem to face the threat that intuits. Perhaps the ,
conflict that McNamara faces is a "reason that must let itself
be reasoned with" (Derrida, Rogues: Two Essays on Reason 159).
In General Curtis Lemay, McNamara faces his threatening
intuitions because Lemay, like Castro, exemplifies the frightful, extremist
will to accelerate the stakes of warfare to the utmost. If McNamara
is troubled by the stakes of moral behavior, by criminality in war, Lemay
embodies the perspective that aggression has no limit when warranted
by the necessity for national self-defense. Taken to these limits, McNamara
reasons, Lemay's military strategy presents a glimpse of the
evil of competitive aggression that may dominate the future.
When evil takes the form of a face so ordinary and so respected, one
must recognize in this face a glimpse of oneself.
Lemay personifies the logic of the nuclear age, a strategic logic
that accelerates the goal driven by the desire to "prevail" over all others. The etymology of "prevail" expresses an absolutism that
predominates before and beyond all else. The will to absolutism
manifested when Lemay besieged Japan in a torrid firestorm, and when he argued
for using nuclear weapons against Cuba in the Cuban Missile Crisis and,
again, against the North Vietnamese in the Vietnam War. He justified
those absolute decisions on practical grounds: if you
have a powerful advantage over your enemy, you should exercise this
force before it is visited on you. Thus the definition of a war criminal
is a general who loses. The problem of needless killing
remains a moral distinction arbitrated by the victor. Both sides must
sacrifice the utmost to prevail. And the sacrifices made for victory
are archived by a victor who is authorized by a morality and a spirituality
underwritten by an absolute, transcendental ideal. Freedom, liberation,
progress, destiny, God are some of the many proper names used to efface
the confusion of needless sacrifice in warfare.
For McNamara, Lemay's strategies of brutal, competitive force
realize the apocalyptic finality of warfare once nuclear armaments proliferate
throughout the world. His repeated response to the force of such hard-line
military and political strategy has been a dedicated effort to persuade
his witnesses to interrupt the sense of entitled "omnipotence"
that disguises a dangerous sense of "vulnerability" that
remains the legacy of the Cold War (Lifton 128). For him, the stakes
of this legacy remain despite historical differences. In fact, his rhetorical
tone has become more urgent. In the May/June 2005 issue of Foreign Policy,
he argues that the Bush Administration's
policy on nuclear weapons continues and contributes to policies that
have been in place for over forty years and that have "grown more
dangerous and diplomatically destructive in the intervening years" ("Apocalypse Soon" 1).
Further, entitled by a sense of omnipotence, the Bush Administration has contributed to the nuclear arms conflict by failing to
ratify the
Comprehensive Test Ban Treaty (CTBT), suggesting that American interests
remain independent of the interests of the international community.
What entitles such authority? McNamara would suggest that such a perspective
of a self-interested power is the effect of hard-line politics of force.
As the strongest nation in the world, the US can dominate the political
sphere and control world history. But we believe that McNamara increasingly
senses that this reason is only part of the reason, meaning that certain
reasons are not reasonable enough.
McNamara cannot quite access the forces of authority that extend Lemay's,
the Bush Administration's, or the U.S.'s historical sense of messianic
dominance. McNamara's thinking encounters a prior,
more formidable violent force that he can barely sense and that he cannot fully know. Yet in
the face of Lemay and others, he is offered a glimpse of
the holocaustal possibility of the messianism of American foreign policy--a future that in its drive toward finality effaces any trace of the
future.
At this impasse, we believe that Derrida's writing provides profound
insight into the violent absolutism that confounds McNamara's
perspective. At this impasse, Jacques Derrida's writing is most memorable
because he has made a compelling claim about the singular force of deconstruction.
Deconstruction has a singular competency in the nuclear
age, for the logic of this era--total remainderless destruction--"watches over deconstruction, guiding its
footsteps" ("No Apocalypse" 27). If deconstruction is anything at all, it intervenes
in those decisive "events which would end any affirmative opening
toward the arrival of the other" (Derrida, "The Deconstruction
of Actuality" 32).
From a Derridean perspective, the nuclear age is a metonymy inscribed
within the structure of ontotheological historicity that Derrida names metaphysics,
the movement of an "absolute epoche" that struggles toward the revelation
of finality ("No Apocalypse" 27). Derrida summarizes the movement
of this particular historicity succinctly when he notes that "the very concept
of history has lived only upon the possibility of meaning, upon the past,
present, or promised presence of meaning and of truth (Derrida, Dissemination
184). The nuclear age is the troubling potential of the internal
logics of transcendence and finality within metaphysical structures that provide complete
revelation in a parousia of truth.
The holocaustal apocalypse of nuclear war would finally
make present the unwitnessable truth of metaphysics: an explosion of negative
transcendence that results from the political efficiency of technocratic
reason, as this decision making economy ultimately prevails in an attempted
capitalization of the absolute. In Derridean terms, such an unveiling
would mean the event of an absolute wholly other revealed within a telos
of deathward closure, which would end all mourning in a "remainderless
destruction . . . completed by a nuclear catastrophe that would irreversibly
destroy the entire archive and all symbolic capacity" (Derrida, "No Apocalypse" 27-28).
What is at issue here . . .is the violence of the archive itself,
as archive, as archival violence. (Derrida, Archive Fever 7)
Nuclear catastrophe would certainly risk annihilating all that is named
humanity. One would not need to read Jacques Derrida's writing to reach
this stunningly obvious conclusion. Catastrophic death is surely not
a horror to be passed over as an obvious simplicity. Nevertheless, Derrida's
point about annihilation directs us to a far more complicated and rewarding
explanation about the metaphysical economy of the absolute--an economy
infected with a trace of evil. What is this trace of evil as such?
When Derrida refers to the destruction of the archive, he writes of
the violent emergence of utter evil. Such a force of evil violently
opposes and destroys all others in its drive to prevail as an absolute:
the "one" (78). Derrida's writing relentlessly traces the
violence of the archive he names western metaphysics, an archive that
sends forth a deathliness in its efforts to enclose or transcend any
trace of its constitutive other. The essence of the nuclear referent
figured by the center, the core, or the basis is the effect of a burning
drive to authorize, elect, dominate, and conclude. Nuclear war is the
legacy of this burning fever.
As the ultimate sacrifice, nuclear war would be the event that finally
reaches to award a name to the unnamable. It would be the war that would
end all confusion.
In confusion, McNamara is constrained by the limit of thinking: he
knows but he does not quite know; and he sees but he cannot see
clearly. He is haunted by the faint image of things burning, and he
hears the murmur of their cries. From where do these images arrive?
Are these things of the past? Are these things now? Are these things
yet to come? At these threatening limits, he trembles in sorrow.
Of the specters that remain with us haunting our writing, of those
that we faintly acknowledge one commands our attention: Its voice echoes: "no apocalypse, not
now."
Notes
1. McNamara
nearly gets the stanza right, but his memory slips on a couple of
words. The correct citation is from Section V of Eliot's Four
Quartets: "We shall not cease from exploration/
And the end of all our exploring/ Will be to arrive where we started/
And know the place for the first time."
2. Errol Morris invented what he calls the "Interrotron" to
help control the gaze of the interviewed subject. The camera
works so that the interviewer's image is directly over the lens, which
structures a conversation between interviewer and interviewee that has
the interviewee looking directly into the camera.
3.In "Four Protocols: Derrida, His Deconstruction,"
John P. Leavey explains how, "in its most general sense, Derrida's deconstruction
can be reduced to a simple phrase: d'une certaine manière, in
a certain way," a phrase Derrida himself uses, in both Writing and
Difference and Of Grammatology, to describe his project
(43).
4. Thus, for example, "Rationality will not save us" (lesson 2),
and yet one must "maximize efficiency," seek "proportionality," "get
the data," and "be prepared to reexamine your reasoning" (lessons 4,
5, 6, and 8). Thus, too, "Belief and seeing are both often wrong" (Morris,
lesson 7); however, not only is it that "There's something beyond one's
self" (lesson 3) but that it is knowable that there is something beyond
oneself. On the one hand, "To do good, you may have to do evil" (lesson
9) because, after all, "you can't change human nature" (Morris, lesson
11); on the other hand, we must "empathize with the enemy" (lesson 1)
and yet must not answer the questions the enemy asks "but the question
you wish had been asked of you" (lesson 10)--which is to say that we must not yield to the
enemy's perspective but insist on our own.
5.The first two lessons involve divergent frames of reference. On
the one hand, the future appears to be apocalyptic, for "the indefinite
combination of human fallibility and nuclear weapons will lead to the
destructions of nations" (lesson 2). On the other hand, we can mitigate
this indefiniteness "by adhering to the principle of a ‘Just War,'
in particular to the principle of proportionality (lesson 1). According
to the first lesson, the destruction of nations is unavoidable. According
to the second, the destruction can be reduced and in any event rendered
more rational and justified. That is, the second posits in a "Just War"
a force of justice that is a matter of a certain calculability. In its
justice, the "Just War" releases a force capable of blocking the incalculable forces associated with human error in making decisions about using nuclear weapons, the
outcomes of which can be predicted to be unpredictable.
Another tension obtains in the way McNamara presents as a solution to
the problem of war what might in fact be part of the problem of war.
On the one hand, "surely we can agree that we should establish as a
major goal of U.S. foreign policy and, indeed, of foreign policies across
the globe: the avoidance in this century of the carnage--160 million
dead--caused by conflict in the 20th century" (lesson 4). On the other hand, however, "one of the greatest dangers we face today
is the risk
that terrorists will obtain access to weapons of mass destruction as
a result of the breakdown of the Non-Proliferation Regime" which "we
in the U.S. are contributing to." (lesson 10). The call to change
"our" policy, however, presupposes not only that "we" can agree that "our"
policy is flawed but that the flaw can be repaired by more rigorously
pursuing the "major goal" of avoiding our or the enemy's reliance on
war. If we can agree, we will not be tempted to engage in the violence
that threatens to erupt from our disagreements.
Lesson 3 requires that the United States try to convince other nations
that its economic, political, and military superiority is to their advantage.
On the one hand, "We are the most powerful nation in the world--economically,
politically, militarily--and we are likely to remain so for decades."
On the other hand, the U.S. should try to "persuade other nations with similar
interests and similar values of our proposed use of that power." The relation of lesson 3 to
lesson 8 restates this tension in terms
of the call to curtail the nation's sovereignty. On the one hand "we
should build a system of jurisprudence based on the International Court
. . . which would hold individuals responsible for crimes against humanity"
(lesson 8). On the other hand "We are the most powerful nation in the
world" (lesson 3) and the U.S. is not likely to relinquish our claim to define,
defend, or otherwise pursue its national self-interests, let alone the
sovereignty on which they are predicated.
Finally, nine of the ten lessons pit the sovereignty of the nation-state
against the non-existent sovereignty of "the human race"--that is, of
"society as a whole." Thus, on the one hand we must act out of
our individual self-sovereignty (lessons 3, 5, 6, 7, 9, 10); on the
other hand, we must act out of our regard for "society as a whole"
(lesson 6), for "the human race" (lesson 1), for "our own poor and .
. . the disadvantaged across the world" (lesson 5).
6. Writing of disaster in general, of a revelation without revelation,
Maurice Blanchot declares that "The disaster ruins everything, all the
while leaving everything intact. It does not touch anyone in particular;
‘I' am not threatened by it, but spared, left aside." In other
words, "There is no reaching the disaster." For this reason, "When the
disaster comes upon us, it does not come" (The Writing of the Disaster,
1). All disasters are disasters of consciousness, of the epistemological
asymmetry between, on the one hand, one consciousness and another (an
I and a you, an I and a he or a she) and, on the other hand, between
the self-conscious, self-reflexive I and an altogether other other, n
another knowing--unknown, unknowable, unattached to self-reflexive subjectivity that says "I,"
hence to an unknowing knowing.
7. Is it that he does not want to say "any more"
(that is, anything additional on the matter) or that he does not want
to say "anymore" (that is, he no longer wants to say what he may have
said in the past)?
8. In explicating Kierkegaard's
reading of Abraham and Isaac, Derrida underscores Kierkegaard's recognition
that "the instant of decision is madness'" (cited in The Gift of
Death 65). In his analysis of Blanchot's recit, "The Instant of
My Death," Derrida endeavors to answer "How is it that the instant makes
testimony both possible and impossible at the same time?" (Demeure 33).
|
|
WHAT YET REMAINS
Every decision is a cut. Every decision is a cut that marks the incalculable decisions that could have been made, the infinite
decisions that didn't make the cut. And all of these remaindered decisions haunt the decisions that, having been made, remain. We
can see, for instance, when we look back upon decisions we have made in our lives, that they are fractured by their possibilities,
that they have always been fractured by the other possibilities, not only the un-chosen possibilities, but even those contingent
on the un-chosen, those to which we are blind in principle. The past, we see, is actually always fractured by the future it cannot
calculate.
For this reason, the Derridean archive would be the repository not only of the future that will come to pass but of those futures that
will not. It would include the trace of what, by virtue of the structure of decision, is without trace.
Born of their cuts. Decisions are born from cutting, by necessity.
"A witness, as such, is always blind. Witnessing substitutes narrative for perception."
--Derrida, Memoirs of the Blind 104.
BLIND TO THE CUT
A film is born of cuts, and bears its cuts, any film, a home movie, a flashy Hollywood production, a documentary film of an historic
decision maker. For a celluloid strip is first cut to pieces before a film can take form: razors, scissors, cisions, and
decisions enjoin in their shredding. Virtually all films are edited in a process of cutting that enables the assembling or the
splicing of the cuts. The reassembly, however, does not restore but continues the violence to temporal
and spatial continuity. Sergei Eisenstein--Soviet socialist filmmaker and innovator of montage--saw political possibilities in the
dialectical conflict in the splice and decided to emphasize it, marking his aesthetic in the cut. At the same time, Hollywood film,
prioritizing narrative structure, perfected "continuity editing," also called "invisible editing," editing that distracts the viewer from
its constitutive cuts to render their necessary visibility "invisible."
EVERY DECISION IS A CUT
Decisions are sometimes marked by their fatal effects, and they are always marked by their fatal origins, their need to have cut off
future possibilities. "We burned to death a hundred thousand Japanese civilians in one night." We see Robert McNamara
say this three times
in The Fog of War. On the third time he asks: "Was there a rule then that said you shouldn't bomb, shouldn't
kill, shouldn't burn to death
100,000 civilians in one night?" Mass killing is obviously traumatic, but it is in the syntactical stutter that McNamara marks
the painful structure of decision itself.
"Blindness does not prohibit tears, it does not deprive one of them."
--Derrida, Memoirs of the Blind 127.
McNamara
is a man who can cry, but, while citing this event three times, he never
cries for the 100,000 Japanese civilians. Yet while we don't quite
see a mourning for those dead, we do catch a glimpse of a mourning of
the decisions not made--the U.S. military could have decided, even,
to "kill" the citizens of Tokyo, but it didn't; it
decided to "burn to death" the citizens of Tokyo. And McNamara
marks this decision over and over. The decision to kill 50-90% of the
urban population of Japan before dropping two atomic bombs on Hiroshima
and Nagasaki was always haunted by the other possible decisions, and
it remains haunted by the other possible decisions. For a decision is
in ruins as soon as it is made, for it sits amidst the ashes of all the unmade decisions, all the futures sacrificed.
Shouldn't
bomb, shouldn't kill, shouldn't burn to death.
"In the beginning, at the origin, there was ruin. At the origin comes ruin; ruin comes to the origin; it is what first comes and happens
to the origin, in the beginning. With no promise of restoration." --Derrida, Memoirs of the
Blind 65.
"That's what's happening right now."
"It's too late."
"It leaves. It leaves." --Derrida, Derrida
(Shouldn't bomb, shouldn't kill, shouldn't burn to death.)
CRITICAL FLICKER FUSION
In film, the stutter becomes a flicker. Consider for a moment that the movement on a roll of film is created by interrupting a
still image 24 times a second, 24 still photographs, each cut with a black bar, a non-image, images and non-images both spooled
through the projector. Yet, we see a continuous, uninterrupted moving image. Humans continue to see an image for a fraction of a
second after it is removed from eyesight, and this is called an "afterimage," a trace of a trace. While we are watching our
afterimage, a black bar, a lapse, a not-seen, crosses the screen. Flick, flick. Forty-eight times a second a projector's light
pulses whose luminosity we perceive as unwavering (Critical Flicker Fusion) . In the flicker is the seen and not seen, what allows
for, but is not itself, seeing. This technical point exemplifies an ethical difficulty. Sight is not just partial; one's vision is
essentially irresponsible to the traces that allow for the presence of vision. There is a constitutive blindness to seeing
because sight has no insight into its own blindness.
HAUNTING POSSIBILITIES
We are necessarily blind. The physiologically blind, we should notice, often reach out to ask other eyes to see in their
blindness.
During his 98 bombing missions in Vietnam, former Captain Randy Floyd never once saw the Vietnamese people who died and
suffered from the bombs dropped from his plane. His job was "very clean," as he says, simply pulling the "commit switch" with the
pre-programmed bomb pattern when it was time. Military performance depends upon decisiveness, upon an unwavering beam of light.
More than anything the "commit switch" cleans up the messy job of decision, blinding one to the incalculable decisions that could
have been made, the incalculable futures sacrificed. The job of the bombardier is the job of a blind man who thinks he can see.
"During the missions, after the missions, the result of what I was doing, the result of this, this game, this, uh, exercise of my
technical expertise never really dawned on me, that reality of the screams, or of the people being blown away, or of their
homeland being destroyed, uh, just was not a part of what I thought about." If he knew he were blind at the time, he would need to
reach out for guidance from another, another whom he himself could not see. Someone looking up and watching a bomb fall from the
sky perhaps. "When I was there, I never saw a child that got burned by napalm."
To see a future clearly requires a blindness, a staving off of possibility. Those sacrificed possibilities can return to haunt,
and they can return to haunt such that we not only are in a position to mourn the sacrifices of the past, but begin to recognize
in the notion of possibility, the necessary sacrifices of the future. "But I look at my children now, and, um, I don't know what
would happen, if, uh, uh, what I would think about if someone napalmed 'em.
Randy Floyd's children haven't been napalmed. But they could be. In opening to his blindness, the Other he can't see, in
recognizing that there will always be Others he can't see, Randy Floyd accesses the Other of infinite possibility. He isn't
recognizing the probability that his children could be burned to death; he is recognizing the possibility. We witness Randy
Floyd's non-witnessing. He knew what he didn't see, a knowledge which opened the possibility of not knowing what he didn't see.
Once one begins to recognize those unseen possibilities, one is experiencing the difference that necessitates mourning. When
Randy Floyd accesses this structure he doesn't mourn the future death of his children as much as he folds that incalculable future
upon a past whose structural difference he then painfully experiences. The past is always fractured by the future it cannot
calculate or see.
Randy Floyd appears in the 1974 documentary Hearts and Minds. We watch his eyes as he speaks, his words forcing
unthinkable images into his mind, seeing what he can't see: Vietnamese children napalmed; his own children napalmed. We watch him
cover his eyes with his hands to wipe the blurring tears. And then, on the screen, we see, cut in, what he didn't: Vietnamese
children, skin peeling off in sheets.
The documentary gives sight to a blindness, what we neglected to mourn, what we never knew to mourn, showing us that there are
endless blindnesses. There is a blindness of the other in all sight. And there is a blindness within mourning that is a
recognition of the other, whose death and whose presence is never fully incorporable, whose death and whose presence we are always
available to, without closure. One can only mourn without promise of restoration.
"They would like to follow the gaze of the other whom they do not see," perhaps even the Other other, the other
who does not return us to ourselves" (Derrida, Memoirs of the Blind 6).
WITH NO PROMISE OF RESTORATION
Documentary film has a history of bringing the unseen into view: it preserves what has passed; it travels to foreign lands; it
serves as exposé; it focuses on the mundane; it represents the marginalized. But before it can serve any of those functions
for viewers, it must be organized by the filmmaker(s). The film must be shredded to pieces before it is assembled into a viewing
experience whose unfolding in time and space we feel to be coherent.
Many films achieve coherence by relying on overarching narrative logic that allows us to experience a series of discontinuous
shots as continuous. In fact, the practice of continuity editing is one of the great hallmarks of Classic Hollywood film.
Continuity editing establishes a number of editing devices that habituate the viewer to experiencing continuity where they see
discontinuity. Something as simple as the shot-reverse shot technique so frequently used when filming a conversation illustrates
this well: we begin with an establishing two-shot of two interlocutors; then we alternate back and forth, usually in close-up,
between the two as they converse--shot-reverse shot. Our sense of narrative continuity--that two people exchange words in a
conversation whose meaning and significance become increasingly clear--overrides the visual discontinuity--that the perspective
hops from one spot to the next without spatial transition and that "dead time" is cut out.
"A witness, as such, is always blind. Witnessing substitutes narrative for perception."
--Derrida, Memoirs of the Blind 104.
While basic continuity style has dominated Hollywood since the early twentieth century, the Hollywood Renaissance cut into this
dominance in the late 1960s, a time of worldwide revolution that included the Vietnam War. A number of American filmmakers began
making experimental and culturally conscious films, many of them violent to narrative expectation. Easy Rider (Hopper
1969) and Bonnie and Clyde (Penn 1967) both famously and abruptly kill their protagonists without resolution or
perhaps even significance; Catch-22 (Nichols 1970), a World War II satire produced during the Vietnam War, often
denies the viewer establishing shots, splicing the viewer instead into disorienting close-ups in medias res; and
M*A*S*H (Altman 1970), a Korean War satire produced during Vietnam, keeps the viewer so far from the central action
that we remain unsure of its centrality. As Warren Beatty astutely observed, "Bob [Altman] had a talent for making the background
come into the foreground and the foreground go into the background, which made the story a lot less linear than it actually was"
(Biskind 103). In other words, American fictional film during the Vietnam War takes up a similar challenge as documentary film
generally: it aims to break our habits of seeing in order to bring to sight forces already at work: discontinuity, disorientation,
non-resolution, uncertainty. These films break from the logic of classical cinematic language. They are marked by their insistence
that we see film in ruins, a representation that in its medium and in its structure always testifies to the violence and division
of its origin.
Derrida's generalization of the ruin in Memoirs of the Blind allows us to see how a film in ruins could speak to an
American culture increasingly threatened by dissent and diversity: "The ruin . . . is experience itself. . . . There is nothing of
the totality that is not immediately opened, pierced, or bored through" (69). The ruin offers "no promise of restoration"
(65).
BLIND SPOTS
Randy Floyd mourns "with no promise of restoration." His own sense of totality has been opened, pierced, bored through.
Robert McNamara's horizon, however, doesn't reveal that choice. His life of war put him in the position of making decisions
so fatal that his understandable response is to hope to provide a structure to relieve the future of seeing this repetition; he
hopes to restore the future with the past.
"At my age, 85, I'm at age where I can look back and derive some conclusions about my actions. My rule has been try to learn, try
to understand what happened. Develop the lessons and pass them on" (Morris).
He quite reasonably suggests a goal:
"Should not the nations of the world--the United States in particular--establish as their overarching foreign policy goal the
reduction of fatalities from conflict within and among nations?" (McNamara, Argument 5)
To help determine the future, McNamara begins digging in the ruins to locate the "missed opportunities" of leaders and decision
makers in conflict.
"I want to be absolutely clear that my primary concern is with raising the probabilities of preventing conflict in the
future. The missed opportunities we examine are, we argue, due primarily to mutual misperception, misunderstanding, and
misjudgment by leaders in Washington and Hanoi. We therefore ask: If each side had known the truth about the other's reality,
might the outcome have been less tragic?" (6).
"As a general rule--a most singular rule, appropriate for dissociating the eye from vision--we are all the more blind to the eye of the
other the more the other shows themselves capable of sight, the more we can exchange a look or a gaze with them." --Derrida, Memoirs
of the Blind 106.
While McNamara recognizes the presence of blind spots in the past, he cannot see their structural necessity. He hopes they can be
illuminated. Within his reasonable world, he has no choice but to work through probabilities. Yet statistical analysis calculates
outcome while it cannot see the incalculable within all outcome, the threateningly incalculable that must be, impossibly,
confronted. The future haunts: those nagging blind spots.
"The point is right away to go beyond, in one fell swoop, the first glance and thus to see there where this
glance is blind, to open one's eyes wide there where one does not see what one sees. One must see, at first sight, what does not
let itself be seen. And this is invisibility itself. For what first sight misses is the invisible. The flaw, the error of first
sight is to see, and not to notice the invisible. --Derrida, Specters of Marx 141.
McNamara's image is already captured, divided by
its future.
"Absolute hospitality requires that I open up my home and that I give not only to the foreigner . . .
but to the absolute, unknown,
anonymous other, and that I give place to them, that I let them come, that I let them arrive, and take place in the place I offer them,
without asking of them either reciprocity (entering into a pact) or even their names." --Derrida, Of
Hospitality 25.
As captured by Morris's documentary, McNamara's struggle with reason and its inadequacy to address futurity
is a strikingly beautiful and painful impasse. Morris takes McNamara's image and renders it through the hesitating fragility of a
blink, that physiological reminder of the weakness of sight, that it shares itself with blindness. The de-centered composition,
dropped frames, freeze frames, and oblique angles all work cinematically to take unwavering self-possession from a man still
looking for the ghosts that will possess him.
"But we are never ourselves, and between us, identical to us, a 'self' is never in itself or identical to
itself." --Derrida, Mémoires 28.
EYES AND TEARS
We are necessarily blind, and we reach out to ask other eyes to see in our blindness. Derrida illustrates this idea simply with
the many portraits of blind men reaching forward with their hands.
In the "Deleted Scenes" from The Fog of War, McNamara cites Dylan Thomas's poem "The Hand that Signed the Paper,"
which ends:
The five kings count the dead but do not soften
The crusted wound nor pat the brow;
A hand rules pity as a hand rules heaven;
Hands have no tears to flow.
The counting hand doesn't reach forward; it stays close to the chest. Hands, here, enlist the dead in their self-enclosing and
instrumental reason. They "see" the dead as a reflection of their own empire and cannot acknowledge the near-dead. But the
blindness of this hand does not cause it to reach out to implore another for assistance. Blind eyes do. Or rather the hands of
those with blind eyes do, for the eyes of the blind no longer service self-navigation, the seeing of oneself in place. The desire
to picture oneself no longer performs through the eyes that are blind.
"The desire for self-presentation is never met, it
never meets up with itself, and that is why the simulacrum takes place. Never does the eye of the Other recall this desire more
sovereignly to the outside and to difference, to the law of disproportion, dissymmetry, and expropriation. And this is memory
itself." --Derrida, Memoirs of the Blind 121.
Even the non-blind find their eyes have deceived them in providing the hope of a glimpse of totality in self.
Self-representational desires, especially at their strongest--for instance, in an act of self-portraiture--reveal the inadequacy
of one's own eyes to actually see oneself seeing. As Derrida write in Memoirs of the Blind: The Self-Portrait and Other
Ruins, the truth of the eyes is unveiled when seeing is veiled, as through tears. For in welling up and delivering forth
tears the eyes are doing something:
"It makes something happen or come, makes something come to the eyes, makes something well up in them, by producing an event. It is
performative, something vision alone would be incapable of if it gave rise only to representational reporting" (122).
At the end of the book, Derrida explains of the Andrew Marvell poem "Eyes and Tears," "between seeing and weeping, he sees between
and catches a glimpse of the difference, he keeps it, looks after it in memory--and this is the veil of tears--until finally, and
from or with the 'same eyes,' the tears see" (128-9):
Thus let your streams o'erflow your springs,
Till eyes and tears be the same things:
And each the other's difference bears;
These weeping eyes, those seeing tears.
The weeping eyes seeing are no longer a repository of (self) representations, but
instead the performative locus of (self) expropriation, no longer an instrument servicing the desire for (self) enclosure.
Catching a glimpse of the difference they weep, and mourn, and cry with joy.
"No justice . . . seems possible or thinkable without the principle of some
responsibility, beyond all living present, within that which disjoins the living present, before the ghosts of those who are not
yet born or who are already dead, be they victims of wars." --Derrida, Specters of Marx
xix.
"Is the most distressing, or even the most deadly infidelity that of a possible mourning which would interiorize within us the image,
idol, or ideal of the other who is dead and only lives in us? Or is it that of the impossible mourning which . . . refuses to take or is
incapable of taking the other within oneself, as in the tomb or the vault of some narcissism?" --Derrida,
Mémoires 6.
No apocalypse. Not now.
"It's too late."
--Derrida, Derrida.
EVERY MOMENT IS MARKED BY THE POSSIBILITY
What is threatening to us is what we cannot--in advance--know, name, or foresee. What is necessary is our opening to alterity, within us
and outside us. Jacques Derrida taught us this forcefully in his lifelong project of recognizing the future as the "arrival of the totally
unexpected," a sentiment introduced early in the documentary bearing his name, Derrida. Later--or was it earlier?--in the
"deleted
interviews" of the film, he recognizes a "death effect" that occurs when one has one's picture taken. Since
the presence of the pro-filmic subject is
not required, but recalled, as the photograph passes through time, photographing always marks an absence: "This film will survive me . . .
every moment is marked by the possibility." One gives oneself over to the monstrous future that includes one's death.
"The desire for self-presentation is never met. . . . Never does the eye of the Other recall this desire more sovereignly to the outside
and to difference, to the law of disproportion, dissymmetry, and expropriation. And this is memory
itself." --Derrida, Memoirs of the Blind 121. Even Derrida shows reluctance. Yet he
finally says, in
Derrida, "at the end there was something good in allowing oneself to be surprised, in allowing other people to take what
they want. It's too late. It leaves; it leaves. That's what's happening right now."
It
leaves. It leaves.
|